The magic money tree problem





.everyoneloves__top-leaderboard:empty,.everyoneloves__mid-leaderboard:empty,.everyoneloves__bot-mid-leaderboard:empty{ margin-bottom:0;
}







15












$begingroup$


I thought of this problem in the shower, it was inspired by investment strategies.



Let's say there was a magic money tree. Every day, you can offer an amount of money to the money tree and it will either triple it, or destroy it with 50/50 probability. You immediately notice that on average you will gain money by doing this and are eager to take advantage of the money tree. However, if you offered all your money at once, you would have a 50% of losing all your money. Unacceptable! You are a pretty risk-averse person, so you decide to come up with a strategy. You want to minimize the odds of losing everything, but you also want to make as much money as you can! You come up with the following: every day, you offer 20% of your current capital to the money tree. Assuming the lowest you can offer is 1 cent, it would take a 31 loss streak to lose all your money if you started with 10 dollars. What's more, the more cash you earn, the longer the losing streak needs to be for you to lose everything, amazing! You quickly start earning loads of cash. But then an idea pops into your head: you can just offer 30% each day and make way more money! But wait, why not offer 35%? 50%? One day, with big dollar signs in your eyes you run up to the money tree with all your millions and offer up 100% of your cash, which the money tree promptly burns. The next day you get a job at McDonalds.



Is there an optimal percentage of your cash you can offer without losing it all?



(sub) questions:



If there is an optimal percentage you should offer, is this static (i.e. 20% every day) or should the percentage grow as your capital increases?



By offering 20% every day, do the odds of losing all your money decrease or increase over time? Is there a percentage of money from where the odds of losing all your money increase over time?










share|cite|improve this question









New contributor




ElectronicToothpick is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.







$endgroup$








  • 7




    $begingroup$
    This seems like a variation on Gambler's ruin
    $endgroup$
    – Robert Long
    Apr 6 at 9:47






  • 2




    $begingroup$
    A lot of this question depends on whether fractional cents are possible. Additionally, there are many possible goals that someone could have in this situation. Different goals would have different optimal strategies.
    $endgroup$
    – Buge
    2 days ago


















15












$begingroup$


I thought of this problem in the shower, it was inspired by investment strategies.



Let's say there was a magic money tree. Every day, you can offer an amount of money to the money tree and it will either triple it, or destroy it with 50/50 probability. You immediately notice that on average you will gain money by doing this and are eager to take advantage of the money tree. However, if you offered all your money at once, you would have a 50% of losing all your money. Unacceptable! You are a pretty risk-averse person, so you decide to come up with a strategy. You want to minimize the odds of losing everything, but you also want to make as much money as you can! You come up with the following: every day, you offer 20% of your current capital to the money tree. Assuming the lowest you can offer is 1 cent, it would take a 31 loss streak to lose all your money if you started with 10 dollars. What's more, the more cash you earn, the longer the losing streak needs to be for you to lose everything, amazing! You quickly start earning loads of cash. But then an idea pops into your head: you can just offer 30% each day and make way more money! But wait, why not offer 35%? 50%? One day, with big dollar signs in your eyes you run up to the money tree with all your millions and offer up 100% of your cash, which the money tree promptly burns. The next day you get a job at McDonalds.



Is there an optimal percentage of your cash you can offer without losing it all?



(sub) questions:



If there is an optimal percentage you should offer, is this static (i.e. 20% every day) or should the percentage grow as your capital increases?



By offering 20% every day, do the odds of losing all your money decrease or increase over time? Is there a percentage of money from where the odds of losing all your money increase over time?










share|cite|improve this question









New contributor




ElectronicToothpick is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.







$endgroup$








  • 7




    $begingroup$
    This seems like a variation on Gambler's ruin
    $endgroup$
    – Robert Long
    Apr 6 at 9:47






  • 2




    $begingroup$
    A lot of this question depends on whether fractional cents are possible. Additionally, there are many possible goals that someone could have in this situation. Different goals would have different optimal strategies.
    $endgroup$
    – Buge
    2 days ago














15












15








15


1



$begingroup$


I thought of this problem in the shower, it was inspired by investment strategies.



Let's say there was a magic money tree. Every day, you can offer an amount of money to the money tree and it will either triple it, or destroy it with 50/50 probability. You immediately notice that on average you will gain money by doing this and are eager to take advantage of the money tree. However, if you offered all your money at once, you would have a 50% of losing all your money. Unacceptable! You are a pretty risk-averse person, so you decide to come up with a strategy. You want to minimize the odds of losing everything, but you also want to make as much money as you can! You come up with the following: every day, you offer 20% of your current capital to the money tree. Assuming the lowest you can offer is 1 cent, it would take a 31 loss streak to lose all your money if you started with 10 dollars. What's more, the more cash you earn, the longer the losing streak needs to be for you to lose everything, amazing! You quickly start earning loads of cash. But then an idea pops into your head: you can just offer 30% each day and make way more money! But wait, why not offer 35%? 50%? One day, with big dollar signs in your eyes you run up to the money tree with all your millions and offer up 100% of your cash, which the money tree promptly burns. The next day you get a job at McDonalds.



Is there an optimal percentage of your cash you can offer without losing it all?



(sub) questions:



If there is an optimal percentage you should offer, is this static (i.e. 20% every day) or should the percentage grow as your capital increases?



By offering 20% every day, do the odds of losing all your money decrease or increase over time? Is there a percentage of money from where the odds of losing all your money increase over time?










share|cite|improve this question









New contributor




ElectronicToothpick is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.







$endgroup$




I thought of this problem in the shower, it was inspired by investment strategies.



Let's say there was a magic money tree. Every day, you can offer an amount of money to the money tree and it will either triple it, or destroy it with 50/50 probability. You immediately notice that on average you will gain money by doing this and are eager to take advantage of the money tree. However, if you offered all your money at once, you would have a 50% of losing all your money. Unacceptable! You are a pretty risk-averse person, so you decide to come up with a strategy. You want to minimize the odds of losing everything, but you also want to make as much money as you can! You come up with the following: every day, you offer 20% of your current capital to the money tree. Assuming the lowest you can offer is 1 cent, it would take a 31 loss streak to lose all your money if you started with 10 dollars. What's more, the more cash you earn, the longer the losing streak needs to be for you to lose everything, amazing! You quickly start earning loads of cash. But then an idea pops into your head: you can just offer 30% each day and make way more money! But wait, why not offer 35%? 50%? One day, with big dollar signs in your eyes you run up to the money tree with all your millions and offer up 100% of your cash, which the money tree promptly burns. The next day you get a job at McDonalds.



Is there an optimal percentage of your cash you can offer without losing it all?



(sub) questions:



If there is an optimal percentage you should offer, is this static (i.e. 20% every day) or should the percentage grow as your capital increases?



By offering 20% every day, do the odds of losing all your money decrease or increase over time? Is there a percentage of money from where the odds of losing all your money increase over time?







probability mathematical-statistics econometrics random-walk martingale






share|cite|improve this question









New contributor




ElectronicToothpick is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.











share|cite|improve this question









New contributor




ElectronicToothpick is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.









share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Apr 6 at 22:24









Martijn Weterings

15k1964




15k1964






New contributor




ElectronicToothpick is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.









asked Apr 6 at 8:59









ElectronicToothpickElectronicToothpick

1814




1814




New contributor




ElectronicToothpick is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.





New contributor





ElectronicToothpick is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.






ElectronicToothpick is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.








  • 7




    $begingroup$
    This seems like a variation on Gambler's ruin
    $endgroup$
    – Robert Long
    Apr 6 at 9:47






  • 2




    $begingroup$
    A lot of this question depends on whether fractional cents are possible. Additionally, there are many possible goals that someone could have in this situation. Different goals would have different optimal strategies.
    $endgroup$
    – Buge
    2 days ago














  • 7




    $begingroup$
    This seems like a variation on Gambler's ruin
    $endgroup$
    – Robert Long
    Apr 6 at 9:47






  • 2




    $begingroup$
    A lot of this question depends on whether fractional cents are possible. Additionally, there are many possible goals that someone could have in this situation. Different goals would have different optimal strategies.
    $endgroup$
    – Buge
    2 days ago








7




7




$begingroup$
This seems like a variation on Gambler's ruin
$endgroup$
– Robert Long
Apr 6 at 9:47




$begingroup$
This seems like a variation on Gambler's ruin
$endgroup$
– Robert Long
Apr 6 at 9:47




2




2




$begingroup$
A lot of this question depends on whether fractional cents are possible. Additionally, there are many possible goals that someone could have in this situation. Different goals would have different optimal strategies.
$endgroup$
– Buge
2 days ago




$begingroup$
A lot of this question depends on whether fractional cents are possible. Additionally, there are many possible goals that someone could have in this situation. Different goals would have different optimal strategies.
$endgroup$
– Buge
2 days ago










4 Answers
4






active

oldest

votes


















16












$begingroup$

This is a well-known problem. It is called a Kelly bet. The answer, by the way, is 1/3rd. It is equivalent to maximizing the log utility of wealth.



Kelly began with taking time to infinity and then solving backward. Since you can always express returns in terms of continuous compounding, then you can also reverse the process and express it in logs. I am going to use the log utility explanation, but the log utility is a convenience. If you are maximizing wealth as $ntoinfty$ then you will end up with a function that works out to be the same as log utility. If $b$ is the payout odds, and $p$ is the probability of winning, and $X$ is the percentage of wealth invested, then the following derivation will work.



For a binary bet, $E(log(X))=plog(1+bX)+(1-p)log(1-X)$, for a single period and unit wealth.



$$frac{d}{dX}{E[log(x)]}=frac{d}{dX}[plog(1+bX)+(1-p)log(1-X)]$$
$$=frac{pb}{1+bX}-frac{1-p}{1-X}$$



Setting the derivative to zero to find the extrema,



$$frac{pb}{1+bX}-frac{1-p}{1-X}=0$$



Cross multiplying, you end up with $$pb(1-X)-(1-p)(1+bX)=0$$
$$pb-pbX-1-bX+p+pbX=0$$
$$bX=pb-1+p$$
$$X=frac{bp-(1-p)}{b}$$



In your case, $$X=frac{3timesfrac{1}{2}-(1-frac{1}{2})}{3}=frac{1}{3}.$$



You can readily expand this to multiple or continuous outcomes by solving the expected utility of wealth over a joint probability distribution, choosing the allocations and subject to any constraints. Interestingly, if you perform it in this manner, by including constraints, such as the ability to meet mortgage payments and so forth, then you have accounted for your total set of risks and so you have a risk-adjusted or at least risk-controlled solution.



Desiderata The actual purpose of the original research had to do with how much to gamble based on a noisy signal. In the specific case, how much to gamble on a noisy electronic signal where it indicated the launch of nuclear weapons by the Soviet Union. There have been several near launches by both the United States and Russia, obviously in error. How much do you gamble on a signal?






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    This strategy would give a higher risk of going broke I think compared to lower fractions
    $endgroup$
    – probabilityislogic
    Apr 7 at 3:18










  • $begingroup$
    @probabilityislogic Only in the case where pennies exist. In the discrete case, it would become true because you could bet your last penny. You couldn't bet a third of a penny. In a discrete world, it is intrinsically true that the probability of bankruptcy must be increasing in allocation size, independent of the payoff case. A 2% allocation has a greater probability of bankruptcy than a 1% in a discrete world.
    $endgroup$
    – Dave Harris
    2 days ago










  • $begingroup$
    @probabilityislogic if you begin with 3 cents then it is risky. If you start with $550 then there is less than one chance in 1024 of going bankrupt. For reasonable pot sizes, the risk of discrete collapse becomes small unless you really go to infinity, then it becomes a certainty unless borrowing is allowed.
    $endgroup$
    – Dave Harris
    2 days ago












  • $begingroup$
    I expected this would be a known problem but I had no clue how to look for it. Thanks for the mention of Kelly. A question though: wikipedia on the kelly criterion mentions the following formula to calculate the optimal percentage: (bp-q)/b. Where b is the #dollars you get on betting 1$, p the probability to win, and q the chance to lose. If I fill this in for my scenario I get: (2*0.5-0.5)/2=0.25. Meaning the optimal percentage to bet would be 25%. What causes this discrepancy with your answer of 1/3rd?
    $endgroup$
    – ElectronicToothpick
    2 days ago






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    @ElectronicToothpick if you fill in b=3 you get 1/3. The difference is in how you consider the three times payout. Say you start with 1 dollar and you bet 50cents, then you consider the triple payout as either ending up with fifty-fifty 50 cents or 2 dollars (b=2, ie minus 50 cents or plus 2 times 50 cents) versus fifty-fifty 50 cents or 2.50 dollars (b=3, ie minus 50 cents or plus 3 times 50 cents).
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    2 days ago





















4












$begingroup$

I don't think this is much different from the Martingale. In your case, there are no doubling bets, but the winning payout is 3x.



I coded a "replica" of your tree. I run 10 simulations. In each simulation (trace), you start with 200 coins and try with the tree, 1 coin each time for 20000 times.



The only conditions that stop the simulation are bankruptcy or having "survived" 20k attempts



enter image description here



So long as the winning odds are 50% or less, sooner or later bankruptcy awaits you.






share|cite|improve this answer








New contributor




Carles Alcolea is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.






$endgroup$









  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Are you able to post the code that you wrote for this as well please?
    $endgroup$
    – baxx
    Apr 6 at 20:19










  • $begingroup$
    This is betting with a constant stake - but betting a fixed proportion of your wealth, such as $frac14$ here, each time would produce a different result. You may need to adapt this to avoid fractional coins (e.g. round down unless this produces a value less than $1$ coin, in which cases bet $1$ coin)
    $endgroup$
    – Henry
    2 days ago





















4












$begingroup$

I liked the answer given by Dave harris. just though I would come at the problem from a "low risk" perspective, rather than profit maximising



The random walk you are doing, assuming your fraction bet is $q$ and probability of winning $p=0.5$ has is given as
$$Y_t|Y_{t-1}=(1-q+3qX_t)Y_{t-1}$$
where $X_tsim Bernoulli(p)$. on average you have
$$E(Y_t|Y_{t-1}) = (1-q+3pq)Y_{t-1}$$
You can iteratively apply this to get
$$Y_t|Y_0=Y_0prod_{j=1}^t (1-q+3qX_t)$$
with expected value
$$E(Y_t|Y_{0}) = (1-q+3pq)^t Y_{0}$$
you can also express the amount at time $t$ as a function of a single random variable $Z_t=sum_{j=1}^t X_tsim Binomial(t,p)$, but noting that $Z_t$ is not independent from $Z_{t-1}$
$$Y_t|Y_0=Y_0 (1+2q)^{Z_t}(1-q)^{t-Z_t}$$



possible strategy



you could use this formula to determine a "low risk" value for $q$. Say assuming you wanted to ensure that after $k$ consecutive losses you still had half your original wealth. Then you set $q=1-2^{-k^{-1}}$



Taking the example $k=5$ means we set $q=0.129$, or with $k=15$ we set $q=0.045$.



Also, due to the recursive nature of the strategy, this risk is what you are taking every at every single bet. That is, at time $s$, by continuing to play you are ensuring that at time $k+s$ your wealth will be at least $0.5Y_{s}$



discussion



the above strategy does not depend on the pay off from winning, but rather about setting a boundary on losing. We can get the expected winnings by substituting in the value for $q$ we calculated, and at the time $k$ that was used with the risk in mind.



however, it is interesting to look at the median rather than expected pay off at time $t$, which can be found by assuming $median(Z_t)approx tp$.
$$Y_k|Y_0=Y_0 (1+2q)^{tp}(1-q)^{t(1-p)}$$
when $p=0.5$ the we have the ratio equal to $(1+q-2q^2)^{0.5t}$. This is maximised when $q=0.25$ and greater than $1$ when $q<0.5$



it is also interesting to calculate the chance you will be ahead at time $t$. to do this we need to determine the value $z$ such that
$$(1+2q)^{z}(1-q)^{t-z}>1$$
doing some rearranging we find that the proportion of wins should satisfy
$$frac{z}{t}>frac{log(1-q)}{log(1-q)-log(1+2q)}$$
This can be plugged into a normal approximation (note: mean of $0.5$ and standard error of $frac{0.5}{sqrt{t}}$) as
$$Pr(text{ahead at time t})approxPhileft(sqrt{t}frac{log(1+2q)+log(1-q)}{left[log(1+2q)-log(1-q)right]}right)$$



which clearly shows the game has very good odds. the factor multiplying $sqrt{t}$ is minimised when $q=0$ (maximised value of $frac{1}{3}$) and is monotonically decreasing as a function of $q$. so the "low risk" strategy is to bet a very small fraction of your wealth, and play a large number of times.



suppose we compare this with $q=frac{1}{3}$ and $q=frac{1}{100}$. the factor for each case is $0.11$ and $0.32$. This means after $38$ games you would have around a 95% chance to be ahead with the small bet, compared to a 75% chance with the larger bet. Additionally, you also have a chance of going broke with the larger bet, assuming you had to round your stake to the nearest 5 cents or dollar. Starting with $20$ this could go $13.35, 8.90,5.95,3.95,2.65,1.75,1.15,0.75,0.50,0.35,0.25,0.15,0.1,0.05,0$.
This is a sequence of $14$ losses out of $38$, and given the game would expect $19$ losses, if you get unlucky with the first few bets, then even winning may not make up for a bad streak (e.g., if most of your wins occur once most of the wealth is gone). going broke with the smaller 1% stake is not possible in $38$ games.
The flip side is that the smaller stake will result in a much smaller profit on average, something like a $350$ fold increase with the large bet compared to $1.2$ increase with the small bet (i.e. you expect to have 24 dollars after 38 rounds with the small bet and 7000 dollars with the large bet).






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    it is if you consider that $q$ is chosen in a low risk manner and we aren't calculating it for $t>>k$, this isn't too bad an approximation. So it is probably overstating the profit from the large betting strategy.
    $endgroup$
    – probabilityislogic
    2 days ago










  • $begingroup$
    Your approach to maximize the median of $Z_t$ is actually the same as the approach from Dave Harris which is maximizing the mean of $Z_t$ (which is the same as the median of $Z_t$). It would be different when one is maximizing the mean of $Y_t$ which is lognormal distributed and for which the mean and median are not the same.
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    yesterday





















2












$begingroup$



Problem statement



Let $Y_t = log_{10}(M_t)$ be the logarithm of the amount of money $M_t$ the gambler has at time $t$.



Let $q$ be the fraction of money that the gambler is betting.



Let $Y_0 = 1$ be the amount of money that the gambler starts with (ten dollars). Let $Y_L=-2$ be the amount of money where the gambler goes bankrupt (below 1 cent). For simplicity we add a rule that the gambler stops gambling when he has passed some amount of money $Y_W$ (we can later lift this rule by taking the limit $Y_W to infty$).



Random walk



You can see the growth and decline of the money as an asymmetric random walk. That is you can describe $Y_t$ as:



$$Y_t = Y_0 + sum_{i=1}^t X_i$$



where



$$mathbb{P}[X_i= a_w =log(1+2q)] = mathbb{P}[X_i= a_l =log(1-q)] = frac{1}{2}$$



Probability of bankruptcy



Martingale



The expression



$$Z_t = c^{Y_t}$$



is a martingale when we choose $c$ such that.



$$c^{a_w}+ c^{a_l} = 2$$ (where $c<1$ if $q<0.5$). Since in that case



$$E[Z_{t+1}] = E[Z_t] frac{1}{2} c^{a_w} + E[Z_t] frac{1}{2} c^{a_l} = E[Z_t]$$



Probability to end up bankrupt



The stopping time (losing/bankruptcy $Y_t < Y_L$ or winning $Y_t>Y_W$) is almost surely finite since it requires in the worst case a winning streak (or losing streak) of a certain finite length, $frac{Y_W-Y_L}{a_w}$, which is almost surely gonna happen.



Then, we can use the optional stopping theorem to say $E[Z_tau]$ at the stopping time $tau$ equals the expected value $E[Z_0]$ at time zero.



Thus



$$c^{Y_0} = E[Z_0] = E[Z_tau] approx mathbb{P}[Y_tau<L] c^{Y_L} + (1-mathbb{P}[Y_tau<L]) c^{Y_W}$$



and



$$ mathbb{P}[Y_tau<Y_L] approx frac{c^{Y_0}-c^{Y_W}}{c^{Y_L}-c^{Y_W}}$$



and the limit $Y_W to infty$



$$ mathbb{P}[Y_tau<Y_L] approx c^{Y_0-Y_L}$$



Conclusions




Is there an optimal percentage of your cash you can offer without losing it all?




Whichever is the optimal percentage will depend on how you value different profits. However, we can say something about the probability to lose it all.



Only when the gambler is betting zero fraction of his money then he will certainly not go bankrupt.



With increasing $q$ the probability to go bankrupt will increase up to some point where the gambler will almost surely go bankrupt within a finite time (the gambler's ruin mentioned by Robert Long in the comments). This point, $q_{text{gambler's ruin}}$, is at $$q_{text{gambler's ruin}} = 1-1/b$$ This is the point where there is no solution for $c$ below one. This is also the point where the increasing steps $a_w$ are smaller than the decreasing steps $a_l$.



Thus, for $b=2$, as long as the gambler bets less than half the money then the gambler will not certainly go bankrupt.




do the odds of losing all your money decrease or increase over time?




The probability to go bankrupt is dependent on the distance from the amount of money where the gambler goes bankrupt. When $q<q_{text{gambler's ruin}}$ the gambler's money will, on average increase, and the probability to go bankrupt will, on average, decrease.



Bankruptcy probability when using the Kelly criterion.



When you use the Kelly criterion mentioned in Dave Harris answer, $q = 0.5(1-1/b)$, for $b$ being the ratio between loss and profit in a single bet, then independent from $b$ the value of $c$ will be equal to $0.1$ and the probability to go bankrupt will be $0.1^{S-L}$.



That is, independent from the assymetry parameter $b$ of the magic tree, the probability to go bankrupt, when using the Kelly criterion, is equal to the ratio of the amount of money where the gambler goes bankrupt and the amount of money that the gambler starts with. For ten dollars and 1 cent this is a 1:1000 probability to go bankrupt, when using the Kelly criterion.



Simulations



The simulations below show different simulated trajectories for different gambling strategies. The red trajectories are ones that ended up bankrupt (hit the line $Y_t=-2$).



simulations



Distribution of profits after time $t$



To further illustrate the possible outcomes of gambling with the money tree, you can model the distribution of $Y_t$ as a one dimensional diffusion process in a homogeneous force field and with an absorbing boundary (where the gambler get's bankrupt). The solution for this situation has been given by Smoluchowski




Smoluchowski, Marian V. "Über Brownsche Molekularbewegung unter Einwirkung äußerer Kräfte und deren Zusammenhang mit der verallgemeinerten Diffusionsgleichung." Annalen der Physik 353.24 (1916): 1103-1112. (online available via: https://www.physik.uni-augsburg.de/theo1/hanggi/History/BM-History.html)



Equation 8:



$$ W(x_0,x,t) = frac{e^{-frac{c(x-x_0)}{2D} - frac{c^2 t}{4D}}}{2 sqrt{pi D t}} left[ e^{-frac{(x-x_0)^2}{4Dt}} - e^{-frac{(x+x_0)^2}{4Dt}} right]$$




This diffusion equation relates to the tree problem when we set the speed $c$ equal to the expected increase $E[Y_t]$, we set $D$ equal to the variance of the change in a single steps $text{Var}(X_t)$, $x_0$ is the initial amount of money, and $t$ is the number of steps.



The image and code below demonstrate the equation:




  • The histogram shows the result from a simulation.


  • The dotted line shows a model when we use a naive normal distribution to approximate the distribution (this corresponds to the absence of the absorbing 'bankruptcy' barrier). This is wrong because some of the results above the bankruptcy level involve trajectories that have passed the bankruptcy level at an earlier time.


  • The continuous line is the approximation using the formula by Smoluchowski.



illustration as diffusion in force field



Codes



#
## Simulations of random walks and bankruptcy:
#

# functions to compute c
cx = function(c,x) {
c^log(1-x,10)+c^log(1+2*x,10) - 2
}
findc = function(x) {
r <- uniroot(cx, c(0,1-0.1^10),x=x,tol=10^-130)
r$root
}


# settings
set.seed(1)
n <- 100000
n2 <- 1000
q <- 0.45

# repeating different betting strategies
for (q in c(0.35,0.4,0.45)) {
# plot empty canvas
plot(1,-1000,
xlim=c(0,n2),ylim=c(-2,50),
type="l",
xlab = "time step", ylab = expression(log[10](M[t])) )

# steps in the logarithm of the money
steps <- c(log(1+2*q,10),log(1-q,10))

# counter for number of bankrupts
bank <- 0

# computing 1000 times
for (i in 1:1000) {
# sampling wins or looses
X_t <- sample(steps, n, replace = TRUE)
# compute log of money
Y_t <- 1+cumsum(X_t)
# compute money
M_t <- 10^Y_t
# optional stopping (bankruptcy)
tau <- min(c(n,which(-2 > Y_t)))
if (tau<n) {
bank <- bank+1
}
# plot only 100 to prevent clutter
if (i<=100) {
col=rgb(tau<n,0,0,0.5)
lines(1:tau,Y_t[1:tau],col=col)
}
}
text(0,45,paste0(bank, " bankruptcies out of 1000 n", "theoretic bankruptcy rate is ", round(findc(q)^3,4)),cex=1,pos=4)
title(paste0("betting a fraction ", round(q,2)))
}

#
## Simulation of histogram of profits/results
#

# settings
set.seed(1)
rep <- 10000 # repetitions for histogram
n <- 5000 # time steps
q <- 0.45 # betting fraction
b <- 2 # betting ratio loss/profit
x0 <- 3 # starting money

# steps in the logarithm of the money
steps <- c(log(1+b*q,10),log(1-q,10))

# to prevent Moiré pattern in
# set binsize to discrete differences in results
binsize <- 2*(steps[1]-steps[2])

for (n in c(200,500,1000)) {

# computing several trials
pays <- rep(0,rep)
for (i in 1:rep) {
# sampling wins or looses
X_t <- sample(steps, n, replace = TRUE)
# you could also make steps according to a normal distribution
# this will give a smoother histogram
# to do this uncomment the line below
# X_t <- rnorm(n,mean(steps),sqrt(0.25*(steps[1]-steps[2])^2))

# compute log of money
Y_t <- x0+cumsum(X_t)
# compute money
M_t <- 10^Y_t
# optional stopping (bankruptcy)
tau <- min(c(n,which(Y_t < 0)))
if (tau<n) {
Y_t[n] <- 0
M_t[n] <- 0
}
pays[i] <- Y_t[n]
}

# histogram
h <- hist(pays[pays>0],
breaks = seq(0,round(2+max(pays)),binsize),
col=rgb(0,0,0,0.5),
ylim=c(0,1200),
xlab = "log(result)", ylab = "counts",
main = "")
title(paste0("after ", n ," steps"),line = 0)

# regular diffusion in a force field (shifted normal distribution)
x <- h$mids
mu <- x0+n*mean(steps)
sig <- sqrt(n*0.25*(steps[1]-steps[2])^2)
lines(x,rep*binsize*(dnorm(x,mu,sig)), lty=2)

# diffusion using the solution by Smoluchowski
# which accounts for absorption
lines(x,rep*binsize*Smoluchowski(x,x0,0.25*(steps[1]-steps[2])^2,mean(steps),n))

}





share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    "That is, independent from the assymetry parameter b of the magic tree, the probability to go bankrupt, when using the Kelly criterion, is equal to the ratio of the amount of money where the gambler goes bankrupt and the amount of money that the gambler starts with. For ten dollars and 1 cent this is a 1:1000 probability to go bankrupt" Im a bit surprised about this. So this means the probability to go bankrupt will be 1:1000 even if the payout is 10 times the offered money per round? How is this possible when the odds of going bankrupt decrease as your money grows?
    $endgroup$
    – ElectronicToothpick
    17 hours ago






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    @ElectronicToothpick If the payout is larger, and if you do not change the fraction that you gamble, then the probability to go bankrupt will be smaller. However, when you increase the fraction that you gamble, then this may not be true anymore. With the Kelly criterion, you will increase the fraction to gamble when the payout is higher. This will increase the expected value of the logarithm of the money, but as a consequence, the probability to go bankrupt will remain the same.
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    14 hours ago








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Actually, when the gambler is not using the Kelly criterion, which optimizes $E[log M_t]$, but instead chooses to optimize $E[M_t]$, then the consequence is that a higher fraction of the amount of money is being gambled. Possibly this might lead to an increase in the risk of bankruptcy when the payout is made larger. I could add an analysis of this, but I am afraid that my answer is already too long and/or complex.
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    14 hours ago














Your Answer





StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
});
});
}, "mathjax-editing");

StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "65"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});

function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: false,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: null,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});


}
});






ElectronicToothpick is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.










draft saved

draft discarded


















StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fstats.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f401480%2fthe-magic-money-tree-problem%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown

























4 Answers
4






active

oldest

votes








4 Answers
4






active

oldest

votes









active

oldest

votes






active

oldest

votes









16












$begingroup$

This is a well-known problem. It is called a Kelly bet. The answer, by the way, is 1/3rd. It is equivalent to maximizing the log utility of wealth.



Kelly began with taking time to infinity and then solving backward. Since you can always express returns in terms of continuous compounding, then you can also reverse the process and express it in logs. I am going to use the log utility explanation, but the log utility is a convenience. If you are maximizing wealth as $ntoinfty$ then you will end up with a function that works out to be the same as log utility. If $b$ is the payout odds, and $p$ is the probability of winning, and $X$ is the percentage of wealth invested, then the following derivation will work.



For a binary bet, $E(log(X))=plog(1+bX)+(1-p)log(1-X)$, for a single period and unit wealth.



$$frac{d}{dX}{E[log(x)]}=frac{d}{dX}[plog(1+bX)+(1-p)log(1-X)]$$
$$=frac{pb}{1+bX}-frac{1-p}{1-X}$$



Setting the derivative to zero to find the extrema,



$$frac{pb}{1+bX}-frac{1-p}{1-X}=0$$



Cross multiplying, you end up with $$pb(1-X)-(1-p)(1+bX)=0$$
$$pb-pbX-1-bX+p+pbX=0$$
$$bX=pb-1+p$$
$$X=frac{bp-(1-p)}{b}$$



In your case, $$X=frac{3timesfrac{1}{2}-(1-frac{1}{2})}{3}=frac{1}{3}.$$



You can readily expand this to multiple or continuous outcomes by solving the expected utility of wealth over a joint probability distribution, choosing the allocations and subject to any constraints. Interestingly, if you perform it in this manner, by including constraints, such as the ability to meet mortgage payments and so forth, then you have accounted for your total set of risks and so you have a risk-adjusted or at least risk-controlled solution.



Desiderata The actual purpose of the original research had to do with how much to gamble based on a noisy signal. In the specific case, how much to gamble on a noisy electronic signal where it indicated the launch of nuclear weapons by the Soviet Union. There have been several near launches by both the United States and Russia, obviously in error. How much do you gamble on a signal?






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    This strategy would give a higher risk of going broke I think compared to lower fractions
    $endgroup$
    – probabilityislogic
    Apr 7 at 3:18










  • $begingroup$
    @probabilityislogic Only in the case where pennies exist. In the discrete case, it would become true because you could bet your last penny. You couldn't bet a third of a penny. In a discrete world, it is intrinsically true that the probability of bankruptcy must be increasing in allocation size, independent of the payoff case. A 2% allocation has a greater probability of bankruptcy than a 1% in a discrete world.
    $endgroup$
    – Dave Harris
    2 days ago










  • $begingroup$
    @probabilityislogic if you begin with 3 cents then it is risky. If you start with $550 then there is less than one chance in 1024 of going bankrupt. For reasonable pot sizes, the risk of discrete collapse becomes small unless you really go to infinity, then it becomes a certainty unless borrowing is allowed.
    $endgroup$
    – Dave Harris
    2 days ago












  • $begingroup$
    I expected this would be a known problem but I had no clue how to look for it. Thanks for the mention of Kelly. A question though: wikipedia on the kelly criterion mentions the following formula to calculate the optimal percentage: (bp-q)/b. Where b is the #dollars you get on betting 1$, p the probability to win, and q the chance to lose. If I fill this in for my scenario I get: (2*0.5-0.5)/2=0.25. Meaning the optimal percentage to bet would be 25%. What causes this discrepancy with your answer of 1/3rd?
    $endgroup$
    – ElectronicToothpick
    2 days ago






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    @ElectronicToothpick if you fill in b=3 you get 1/3. The difference is in how you consider the three times payout. Say you start with 1 dollar and you bet 50cents, then you consider the triple payout as either ending up with fifty-fifty 50 cents or 2 dollars (b=2, ie minus 50 cents or plus 2 times 50 cents) versus fifty-fifty 50 cents or 2.50 dollars (b=3, ie minus 50 cents or plus 3 times 50 cents).
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    2 days ago


















16












$begingroup$

This is a well-known problem. It is called a Kelly bet. The answer, by the way, is 1/3rd. It is equivalent to maximizing the log utility of wealth.



Kelly began with taking time to infinity and then solving backward. Since you can always express returns in terms of continuous compounding, then you can also reverse the process and express it in logs. I am going to use the log utility explanation, but the log utility is a convenience. If you are maximizing wealth as $ntoinfty$ then you will end up with a function that works out to be the same as log utility. If $b$ is the payout odds, and $p$ is the probability of winning, and $X$ is the percentage of wealth invested, then the following derivation will work.



For a binary bet, $E(log(X))=plog(1+bX)+(1-p)log(1-X)$, for a single period and unit wealth.



$$frac{d}{dX}{E[log(x)]}=frac{d}{dX}[plog(1+bX)+(1-p)log(1-X)]$$
$$=frac{pb}{1+bX}-frac{1-p}{1-X}$$



Setting the derivative to zero to find the extrema,



$$frac{pb}{1+bX}-frac{1-p}{1-X}=0$$



Cross multiplying, you end up with $$pb(1-X)-(1-p)(1+bX)=0$$
$$pb-pbX-1-bX+p+pbX=0$$
$$bX=pb-1+p$$
$$X=frac{bp-(1-p)}{b}$$



In your case, $$X=frac{3timesfrac{1}{2}-(1-frac{1}{2})}{3}=frac{1}{3}.$$



You can readily expand this to multiple or continuous outcomes by solving the expected utility of wealth over a joint probability distribution, choosing the allocations and subject to any constraints. Interestingly, if you perform it in this manner, by including constraints, such as the ability to meet mortgage payments and so forth, then you have accounted for your total set of risks and so you have a risk-adjusted or at least risk-controlled solution.



Desiderata The actual purpose of the original research had to do with how much to gamble based on a noisy signal. In the specific case, how much to gamble on a noisy electronic signal where it indicated the launch of nuclear weapons by the Soviet Union. There have been several near launches by both the United States and Russia, obviously in error. How much do you gamble on a signal?






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    This strategy would give a higher risk of going broke I think compared to lower fractions
    $endgroup$
    – probabilityislogic
    Apr 7 at 3:18










  • $begingroup$
    @probabilityislogic Only in the case where pennies exist. In the discrete case, it would become true because you could bet your last penny. You couldn't bet a third of a penny. In a discrete world, it is intrinsically true that the probability of bankruptcy must be increasing in allocation size, independent of the payoff case. A 2% allocation has a greater probability of bankruptcy than a 1% in a discrete world.
    $endgroup$
    – Dave Harris
    2 days ago










  • $begingroup$
    @probabilityislogic if you begin with 3 cents then it is risky. If you start with $550 then there is less than one chance in 1024 of going bankrupt. For reasonable pot sizes, the risk of discrete collapse becomes small unless you really go to infinity, then it becomes a certainty unless borrowing is allowed.
    $endgroup$
    – Dave Harris
    2 days ago












  • $begingroup$
    I expected this would be a known problem but I had no clue how to look for it. Thanks for the mention of Kelly. A question though: wikipedia on the kelly criterion mentions the following formula to calculate the optimal percentage: (bp-q)/b. Where b is the #dollars you get on betting 1$, p the probability to win, and q the chance to lose. If I fill this in for my scenario I get: (2*0.5-0.5)/2=0.25. Meaning the optimal percentage to bet would be 25%. What causes this discrepancy with your answer of 1/3rd?
    $endgroup$
    – ElectronicToothpick
    2 days ago






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    @ElectronicToothpick if you fill in b=3 you get 1/3. The difference is in how you consider the three times payout. Say you start with 1 dollar and you bet 50cents, then you consider the triple payout as either ending up with fifty-fifty 50 cents or 2 dollars (b=2, ie minus 50 cents or plus 2 times 50 cents) versus fifty-fifty 50 cents or 2.50 dollars (b=3, ie minus 50 cents or plus 3 times 50 cents).
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    2 days ago
















16












16








16





$begingroup$

This is a well-known problem. It is called a Kelly bet. The answer, by the way, is 1/3rd. It is equivalent to maximizing the log utility of wealth.



Kelly began with taking time to infinity and then solving backward. Since you can always express returns in terms of continuous compounding, then you can also reverse the process and express it in logs. I am going to use the log utility explanation, but the log utility is a convenience. If you are maximizing wealth as $ntoinfty$ then you will end up with a function that works out to be the same as log utility. If $b$ is the payout odds, and $p$ is the probability of winning, and $X$ is the percentage of wealth invested, then the following derivation will work.



For a binary bet, $E(log(X))=plog(1+bX)+(1-p)log(1-X)$, for a single period and unit wealth.



$$frac{d}{dX}{E[log(x)]}=frac{d}{dX}[plog(1+bX)+(1-p)log(1-X)]$$
$$=frac{pb}{1+bX}-frac{1-p}{1-X}$$



Setting the derivative to zero to find the extrema,



$$frac{pb}{1+bX}-frac{1-p}{1-X}=0$$



Cross multiplying, you end up with $$pb(1-X)-(1-p)(1+bX)=0$$
$$pb-pbX-1-bX+p+pbX=0$$
$$bX=pb-1+p$$
$$X=frac{bp-(1-p)}{b}$$



In your case, $$X=frac{3timesfrac{1}{2}-(1-frac{1}{2})}{3}=frac{1}{3}.$$



You can readily expand this to multiple or continuous outcomes by solving the expected utility of wealth over a joint probability distribution, choosing the allocations and subject to any constraints. Interestingly, if you perform it in this manner, by including constraints, such as the ability to meet mortgage payments and so forth, then you have accounted for your total set of risks and so you have a risk-adjusted or at least risk-controlled solution.



Desiderata The actual purpose of the original research had to do with how much to gamble based on a noisy signal. In the specific case, how much to gamble on a noisy electronic signal where it indicated the launch of nuclear weapons by the Soviet Union. There have been several near launches by both the United States and Russia, obviously in error. How much do you gamble on a signal?






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$



This is a well-known problem. It is called a Kelly bet. The answer, by the way, is 1/3rd. It is equivalent to maximizing the log utility of wealth.



Kelly began with taking time to infinity and then solving backward. Since you can always express returns in terms of continuous compounding, then you can also reverse the process and express it in logs. I am going to use the log utility explanation, but the log utility is a convenience. If you are maximizing wealth as $ntoinfty$ then you will end up with a function that works out to be the same as log utility. If $b$ is the payout odds, and $p$ is the probability of winning, and $X$ is the percentage of wealth invested, then the following derivation will work.



For a binary bet, $E(log(X))=plog(1+bX)+(1-p)log(1-X)$, for a single period and unit wealth.



$$frac{d}{dX}{E[log(x)]}=frac{d}{dX}[plog(1+bX)+(1-p)log(1-X)]$$
$$=frac{pb}{1+bX}-frac{1-p}{1-X}$$



Setting the derivative to zero to find the extrema,



$$frac{pb}{1+bX}-frac{1-p}{1-X}=0$$



Cross multiplying, you end up with $$pb(1-X)-(1-p)(1+bX)=0$$
$$pb-pbX-1-bX+p+pbX=0$$
$$bX=pb-1+p$$
$$X=frac{bp-(1-p)}{b}$$



In your case, $$X=frac{3timesfrac{1}{2}-(1-frac{1}{2})}{3}=frac{1}{3}.$$



You can readily expand this to multiple or continuous outcomes by solving the expected utility of wealth over a joint probability distribution, choosing the allocations and subject to any constraints. Interestingly, if you perform it in this manner, by including constraints, such as the ability to meet mortgage payments and so forth, then you have accounted for your total set of risks and so you have a risk-adjusted or at least risk-controlled solution.



Desiderata The actual purpose of the original research had to do with how much to gamble based on a noisy signal. In the specific case, how much to gamble on a noisy electronic signal where it indicated the launch of nuclear weapons by the Soviet Union. There have been several near launches by both the United States and Russia, obviously in error. How much do you gamble on a signal?







share|cite|improve this answer












share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer










answered Apr 6 at 23:12









Dave HarrisDave Harris

3,942516




3,942516












  • $begingroup$
    This strategy would give a higher risk of going broke I think compared to lower fractions
    $endgroup$
    – probabilityislogic
    Apr 7 at 3:18










  • $begingroup$
    @probabilityislogic Only in the case where pennies exist. In the discrete case, it would become true because you could bet your last penny. You couldn't bet a third of a penny. In a discrete world, it is intrinsically true that the probability of bankruptcy must be increasing in allocation size, independent of the payoff case. A 2% allocation has a greater probability of bankruptcy than a 1% in a discrete world.
    $endgroup$
    – Dave Harris
    2 days ago










  • $begingroup$
    @probabilityislogic if you begin with 3 cents then it is risky. If you start with $550 then there is less than one chance in 1024 of going bankrupt. For reasonable pot sizes, the risk of discrete collapse becomes small unless you really go to infinity, then it becomes a certainty unless borrowing is allowed.
    $endgroup$
    – Dave Harris
    2 days ago












  • $begingroup$
    I expected this would be a known problem but I had no clue how to look for it. Thanks for the mention of Kelly. A question though: wikipedia on the kelly criterion mentions the following formula to calculate the optimal percentage: (bp-q)/b. Where b is the #dollars you get on betting 1$, p the probability to win, and q the chance to lose. If I fill this in for my scenario I get: (2*0.5-0.5)/2=0.25. Meaning the optimal percentage to bet would be 25%. What causes this discrepancy with your answer of 1/3rd?
    $endgroup$
    – ElectronicToothpick
    2 days ago






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    @ElectronicToothpick if you fill in b=3 you get 1/3. The difference is in how you consider the three times payout. Say you start with 1 dollar and you bet 50cents, then you consider the triple payout as either ending up with fifty-fifty 50 cents or 2 dollars (b=2, ie minus 50 cents or plus 2 times 50 cents) versus fifty-fifty 50 cents or 2.50 dollars (b=3, ie minus 50 cents or plus 3 times 50 cents).
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    2 days ago




















  • $begingroup$
    This strategy would give a higher risk of going broke I think compared to lower fractions
    $endgroup$
    – probabilityislogic
    Apr 7 at 3:18










  • $begingroup$
    @probabilityislogic Only in the case where pennies exist. In the discrete case, it would become true because you could bet your last penny. You couldn't bet a third of a penny. In a discrete world, it is intrinsically true that the probability of bankruptcy must be increasing in allocation size, independent of the payoff case. A 2% allocation has a greater probability of bankruptcy than a 1% in a discrete world.
    $endgroup$
    – Dave Harris
    2 days ago










  • $begingroup$
    @probabilityislogic if you begin with 3 cents then it is risky. If you start with $550 then there is less than one chance in 1024 of going bankrupt. For reasonable pot sizes, the risk of discrete collapse becomes small unless you really go to infinity, then it becomes a certainty unless borrowing is allowed.
    $endgroup$
    – Dave Harris
    2 days ago












  • $begingroup$
    I expected this would be a known problem but I had no clue how to look for it. Thanks for the mention of Kelly. A question though: wikipedia on the kelly criterion mentions the following formula to calculate the optimal percentage: (bp-q)/b. Where b is the #dollars you get on betting 1$, p the probability to win, and q the chance to lose. If I fill this in for my scenario I get: (2*0.5-0.5)/2=0.25. Meaning the optimal percentage to bet would be 25%. What causes this discrepancy with your answer of 1/3rd?
    $endgroup$
    – ElectronicToothpick
    2 days ago






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    @ElectronicToothpick if you fill in b=3 you get 1/3. The difference is in how you consider the three times payout. Say you start with 1 dollar and you bet 50cents, then you consider the triple payout as either ending up with fifty-fifty 50 cents or 2 dollars (b=2, ie minus 50 cents or plus 2 times 50 cents) versus fifty-fifty 50 cents or 2.50 dollars (b=3, ie minus 50 cents or plus 3 times 50 cents).
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    2 days ago


















$begingroup$
This strategy would give a higher risk of going broke I think compared to lower fractions
$endgroup$
– probabilityislogic
Apr 7 at 3:18




$begingroup$
This strategy would give a higher risk of going broke I think compared to lower fractions
$endgroup$
– probabilityislogic
Apr 7 at 3:18












$begingroup$
@probabilityislogic Only in the case where pennies exist. In the discrete case, it would become true because you could bet your last penny. You couldn't bet a third of a penny. In a discrete world, it is intrinsically true that the probability of bankruptcy must be increasing in allocation size, independent of the payoff case. A 2% allocation has a greater probability of bankruptcy than a 1% in a discrete world.
$endgroup$
– Dave Harris
2 days ago




$begingroup$
@probabilityislogic Only in the case where pennies exist. In the discrete case, it would become true because you could bet your last penny. You couldn't bet a third of a penny. In a discrete world, it is intrinsically true that the probability of bankruptcy must be increasing in allocation size, independent of the payoff case. A 2% allocation has a greater probability of bankruptcy than a 1% in a discrete world.
$endgroup$
– Dave Harris
2 days ago












$begingroup$
@probabilityislogic if you begin with 3 cents then it is risky. If you start with $550 then there is less than one chance in 1024 of going bankrupt. For reasonable pot sizes, the risk of discrete collapse becomes small unless you really go to infinity, then it becomes a certainty unless borrowing is allowed.
$endgroup$
– Dave Harris
2 days ago






$begingroup$
@probabilityislogic if you begin with 3 cents then it is risky. If you start with $550 then there is less than one chance in 1024 of going bankrupt. For reasonable pot sizes, the risk of discrete collapse becomes small unless you really go to infinity, then it becomes a certainty unless borrowing is allowed.
$endgroup$
– Dave Harris
2 days ago














$begingroup$
I expected this would be a known problem but I had no clue how to look for it. Thanks for the mention of Kelly. A question though: wikipedia on the kelly criterion mentions the following formula to calculate the optimal percentage: (bp-q)/b. Where b is the #dollars you get on betting 1$, p the probability to win, and q the chance to lose. If I fill this in for my scenario I get: (2*0.5-0.5)/2=0.25. Meaning the optimal percentage to bet would be 25%. What causes this discrepancy with your answer of 1/3rd?
$endgroup$
– ElectronicToothpick
2 days ago




$begingroup$
I expected this would be a known problem but I had no clue how to look for it. Thanks for the mention of Kelly. A question though: wikipedia on the kelly criterion mentions the following formula to calculate the optimal percentage: (bp-q)/b. Where b is the #dollars you get on betting 1$, p the probability to win, and q the chance to lose. If I fill this in for my scenario I get: (2*0.5-0.5)/2=0.25. Meaning the optimal percentage to bet would be 25%. What causes this discrepancy with your answer of 1/3rd?
$endgroup$
– ElectronicToothpick
2 days ago




3




3




$begingroup$
@ElectronicToothpick if you fill in b=3 you get 1/3. The difference is in how you consider the three times payout. Say you start with 1 dollar and you bet 50cents, then you consider the triple payout as either ending up with fifty-fifty 50 cents or 2 dollars (b=2, ie minus 50 cents or plus 2 times 50 cents) versus fifty-fifty 50 cents or 2.50 dollars (b=3, ie minus 50 cents or plus 3 times 50 cents).
$endgroup$
– Martijn Weterings
2 days ago






$begingroup$
@ElectronicToothpick if you fill in b=3 you get 1/3. The difference is in how you consider the three times payout. Say you start with 1 dollar and you bet 50cents, then you consider the triple payout as either ending up with fifty-fifty 50 cents or 2 dollars (b=2, ie minus 50 cents or plus 2 times 50 cents) versus fifty-fifty 50 cents or 2.50 dollars (b=3, ie minus 50 cents or plus 3 times 50 cents).
$endgroup$
– Martijn Weterings
2 days ago















4












$begingroup$

I don't think this is much different from the Martingale. In your case, there are no doubling bets, but the winning payout is 3x.



I coded a "replica" of your tree. I run 10 simulations. In each simulation (trace), you start with 200 coins and try with the tree, 1 coin each time for 20000 times.



The only conditions that stop the simulation are bankruptcy or having "survived" 20k attempts



enter image description here



So long as the winning odds are 50% or less, sooner or later bankruptcy awaits you.






share|cite|improve this answer








New contributor




Carles Alcolea is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.






$endgroup$









  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Are you able to post the code that you wrote for this as well please?
    $endgroup$
    – baxx
    Apr 6 at 20:19










  • $begingroup$
    This is betting with a constant stake - but betting a fixed proportion of your wealth, such as $frac14$ here, each time would produce a different result. You may need to adapt this to avoid fractional coins (e.g. round down unless this produces a value less than $1$ coin, in which cases bet $1$ coin)
    $endgroup$
    – Henry
    2 days ago


















4












$begingroup$

I don't think this is much different from the Martingale. In your case, there are no doubling bets, but the winning payout is 3x.



I coded a "replica" of your tree. I run 10 simulations. In each simulation (trace), you start with 200 coins and try with the tree, 1 coin each time for 20000 times.



The only conditions that stop the simulation are bankruptcy or having "survived" 20k attempts



enter image description here



So long as the winning odds are 50% or less, sooner or later bankruptcy awaits you.






share|cite|improve this answer








New contributor




Carles Alcolea is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.






$endgroup$









  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Are you able to post the code that you wrote for this as well please?
    $endgroup$
    – baxx
    Apr 6 at 20:19










  • $begingroup$
    This is betting with a constant stake - but betting a fixed proportion of your wealth, such as $frac14$ here, each time would produce a different result. You may need to adapt this to avoid fractional coins (e.g. round down unless this produces a value less than $1$ coin, in which cases bet $1$ coin)
    $endgroup$
    – Henry
    2 days ago
















4












4








4





$begingroup$

I don't think this is much different from the Martingale. In your case, there are no doubling bets, but the winning payout is 3x.



I coded a "replica" of your tree. I run 10 simulations. In each simulation (trace), you start with 200 coins and try with the tree, 1 coin each time for 20000 times.



The only conditions that stop the simulation are bankruptcy or having "survived" 20k attempts



enter image description here



So long as the winning odds are 50% or less, sooner or later bankruptcy awaits you.






share|cite|improve this answer








New contributor




Carles Alcolea is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.






$endgroup$



I don't think this is much different from the Martingale. In your case, there are no doubling bets, but the winning payout is 3x.



I coded a "replica" of your tree. I run 10 simulations. In each simulation (trace), you start with 200 coins and try with the tree, 1 coin each time for 20000 times.



The only conditions that stop the simulation are bankruptcy or having "survived" 20k attempts



enter image description here



So long as the winning odds are 50% or less, sooner or later bankruptcy awaits you.







share|cite|improve this answer








New contributor




Carles Alcolea is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.









share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer






New contributor




Carles Alcolea is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.









answered Apr 6 at 18:07









Carles AlcoleaCarles Alcolea

1492




1492




New contributor




Carles Alcolea is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.





New contributor





Carles Alcolea is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.






Carles Alcolea is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Are you able to post the code that you wrote for this as well please?
    $endgroup$
    – baxx
    Apr 6 at 20:19










  • $begingroup$
    This is betting with a constant stake - but betting a fixed proportion of your wealth, such as $frac14$ here, each time would produce a different result. You may need to adapt this to avoid fractional coins (e.g. round down unless this produces a value less than $1$ coin, in which cases bet $1$ coin)
    $endgroup$
    – Henry
    2 days ago
















  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Are you able to post the code that you wrote for this as well please?
    $endgroup$
    – baxx
    Apr 6 at 20:19










  • $begingroup$
    This is betting with a constant stake - but betting a fixed proportion of your wealth, such as $frac14$ here, each time would produce a different result. You may need to adapt this to avoid fractional coins (e.g. round down unless this produces a value less than $1$ coin, in which cases bet $1$ coin)
    $endgroup$
    – Henry
    2 days ago










1




1




$begingroup$
Are you able to post the code that you wrote for this as well please?
$endgroup$
– baxx
Apr 6 at 20:19




$begingroup$
Are you able to post the code that you wrote for this as well please?
$endgroup$
– baxx
Apr 6 at 20:19












$begingroup$
This is betting with a constant stake - but betting a fixed proportion of your wealth, such as $frac14$ here, each time would produce a different result. You may need to adapt this to avoid fractional coins (e.g. round down unless this produces a value less than $1$ coin, in which cases bet $1$ coin)
$endgroup$
– Henry
2 days ago






$begingroup$
This is betting with a constant stake - but betting a fixed proportion of your wealth, such as $frac14$ here, each time would produce a different result. You may need to adapt this to avoid fractional coins (e.g. round down unless this produces a value less than $1$ coin, in which cases bet $1$ coin)
$endgroup$
– Henry
2 days ago













4












$begingroup$

I liked the answer given by Dave harris. just though I would come at the problem from a "low risk" perspective, rather than profit maximising



The random walk you are doing, assuming your fraction bet is $q$ and probability of winning $p=0.5$ has is given as
$$Y_t|Y_{t-1}=(1-q+3qX_t)Y_{t-1}$$
where $X_tsim Bernoulli(p)$. on average you have
$$E(Y_t|Y_{t-1}) = (1-q+3pq)Y_{t-1}$$
You can iteratively apply this to get
$$Y_t|Y_0=Y_0prod_{j=1}^t (1-q+3qX_t)$$
with expected value
$$E(Y_t|Y_{0}) = (1-q+3pq)^t Y_{0}$$
you can also express the amount at time $t$ as a function of a single random variable $Z_t=sum_{j=1}^t X_tsim Binomial(t,p)$, but noting that $Z_t$ is not independent from $Z_{t-1}$
$$Y_t|Y_0=Y_0 (1+2q)^{Z_t}(1-q)^{t-Z_t}$$



possible strategy



you could use this formula to determine a "low risk" value for $q$. Say assuming you wanted to ensure that after $k$ consecutive losses you still had half your original wealth. Then you set $q=1-2^{-k^{-1}}$



Taking the example $k=5$ means we set $q=0.129$, or with $k=15$ we set $q=0.045$.



Also, due to the recursive nature of the strategy, this risk is what you are taking every at every single bet. That is, at time $s$, by continuing to play you are ensuring that at time $k+s$ your wealth will be at least $0.5Y_{s}$



discussion



the above strategy does not depend on the pay off from winning, but rather about setting a boundary on losing. We can get the expected winnings by substituting in the value for $q$ we calculated, and at the time $k$ that was used with the risk in mind.



however, it is interesting to look at the median rather than expected pay off at time $t$, which can be found by assuming $median(Z_t)approx tp$.
$$Y_k|Y_0=Y_0 (1+2q)^{tp}(1-q)^{t(1-p)}$$
when $p=0.5$ the we have the ratio equal to $(1+q-2q^2)^{0.5t}$. This is maximised when $q=0.25$ and greater than $1$ when $q<0.5$



it is also interesting to calculate the chance you will be ahead at time $t$. to do this we need to determine the value $z$ such that
$$(1+2q)^{z}(1-q)^{t-z}>1$$
doing some rearranging we find that the proportion of wins should satisfy
$$frac{z}{t}>frac{log(1-q)}{log(1-q)-log(1+2q)}$$
This can be plugged into a normal approximation (note: mean of $0.5$ and standard error of $frac{0.5}{sqrt{t}}$) as
$$Pr(text{ahead at time t})approxPhileft(sqrt{t}frac{log(1+2q)+log(1-q)}{left[log(1+2q)-log(1-q)right]}right)$$



which clearly shows the game has very good odds. the factor multiplying $sqrt{t}$ is minimised when $q=0$ (maximised value of $frac{1}{3}$) and is monotonically decreasing as a function of $q$. so the "low risk" strategy is to bet a very small fraction of your wealth, and play a large number of times.



suppose we compare this with $q=frac{1}{3}$ and $q=frac{1}{100}$. the factor for each case is $0.11$ and $0.32$. This means after $38$ games you would have around a 95% chance to be ahead with the small bet, compared to a 75% chance with the larger bet. Additionally, you also have a chance of going broke with the larger bet, assuming you had to round your stake to the nearest 5 cents or dollar. Starting with $20$ this could go $13.35, 8.90,5.95,3.95,2.65,1.75,1.15,0.75,0.50,0.35,0.25,0.15,0.1,0.05,0$.
This is a sequence of $14$ losses out of $38$, and given the game would expect $19$ losses, if you get unlucky with the first few bets, then even winning may not make up for a bad streak (e.g., if most of your wins occur once most of the wealth is gone). going broke with the smaller 1% stake is not possible in $38$ games.
The flip side is that the smaller stake will result in a much smaller profit on average, something like a $350$ fold increase with the large bet compared to $1.2$ increase with the small bet (i.e. you expect to have 24 dollars after 38 rounds with the small bet and 7000 dollars with the large bet).






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    it is if you consider that $q$ is chosen in a low risk manner and we aren't calculating it for $t>>k$, this isn't too bad an approximation. So it is probably overstating the profit from the large betting strategy.
    $endgroup$
    – probabilityislogic
    2 days ago










  • $begingroup$
    Your approach to maximize the median of $Z_t$ is actually the same as the approach from Dave Harris which is maximizing the mean of $Z_t$ (which is the same as the median of $Z_t$). It would be different when one is maximizing the mean of $Y_t$ which is lognormal distributed and for which the mean and median are not the same.
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    yesterday


















4












$begingroup$

I liked the answer given by Dave harris. just though I would come at the problem from a "low risk" perspective, rather than profit maximising



The random walk you are doing, assuming your fraction bet is $q$ and probability of winning $p=0.5$ has is given as
$$Y_t|Y_{t-1}=(1-q+3qX_t)Y_{t-1}$$
where $X_tsim Bernoulli(p)$. on average you have
$$E(Y_t|Y_{t-1}) = (1-q+3pq)Y_{t-1}$$
You can iteratively apply this to get
$$Y_t|Y_0=Y_0prod_{j=1}^t (1-q+3qX_t)$$
with expected value
$$E(Y_t|Y_{0}) = (1-q+3pq)^t Y_{0}$$
you can also express the amount at time $t$ as a function of a single random variable $Z_t=sum_{j=1}^t X_tsim Binomial(t,p)$, but noting that $Z_t$ is not independent from $Z_{t-1}$
$$Y_t|Y_0=Y_0 (1+2q)^{Z_t}(1-q)^{t-Z_t}$$



possible strategy



you could use this formula to determine a "low risk" value for $q$. Say assuming you wanted to ensure that after $k$ consecutive losses you still had half your original wealth. Then you set $q=1-2^{-k^{-1}}$



Taking the example $k=5$ means we set $q=0.129$, or with $k=15$ we set $q=0.045$.



Also, due to the recursive nature of the strategy, this risk is what you are taking every at every single bet. That is, at time $s$, by continuing to play you are ensuring that at time $k+s$ your wealth will be at least $0.5Y_{s}$



discussion



the above strategy does not depend on the pay off from winning, but rather about setting a boundary on losing. We can get the expected winnings by substituting in the value for $q$ we calculated, and at the time $k$ that was used with the risk in mind.



however, it is interesting to look at the median rather than expected pay off at time $t$, which can be found by assuming $median(Z_t)approx tp$.
$$Y_k|Y_0=Y_0 (1+2q)^{tp}(1-q)^{t(1-p)}$$
when $p=0.5$ the we have the ratio equal to $(1+q-2q^2)^{0.5t}$. This is maximised when $q=0.25$ and greater than $1$ when $q<0.5$



it is also interesting to calculate the chance you will be ahead at time $t$. to do this we need to determine the value $z$ such that
$$(1+2q)^{z}(1-q)^{t-z}>1$$
doing some rearranging we find that the proportion of wins should satisfy
$$frac{z}{t}>frac{log(1-q)}{log(1-q)-log(1+2q)}$$
This can be plugged into a normal approximation (note: mean of $0.5$ and standard error of $frac{0.5}{sqrt{t}}$) as
$$Pr(text{ahead at time t})approxPhileft(sqrt{t}frac{log(1+2q)+log(1-q)}{left[log(1+2q)-log(1-q)right]}right)$$



which clearly shows the game has very good odds. the factor multiplying $sqrt{t}$ is minimised when $q=0$ (maximised value of $frac{1}{3}$) and is monotonically decreasing as a function of $q$. so the "low risk" strategy is to bet a very small fraction of your wealth, and play a large number of times.



suppose we compare this with $q=frac{1}{3}$ and $q=frac{1}{100}$. the factor for each case is $0.11$ and $0.32$. This means after $38$ games you would have around a 95% chance to be ahead with the small bet, compared to a 75% chance with the larger bet. Additionally, you also have a chance of going broke with the larger bet, assuming you had to round your stake to the nearest 5 cents or dollar. Starting with $20$ this could go $13.35, 8.90,5.95,3.95,2.65,1.75,1.15,0.75,0.50,0.35,0.25,0.15,0.1,0.05,0$.
This is a sequence of $14$ losses out of $38$, and given the game would expect $19$ losses, if you get unlucky with the first few bets, then even winning may not make up for a bad streak (e.g., if most of your wins occur once most of the wealth is gone). going broke with the smaller 1% stake is not possible in $38$ games.
The flip side is that the smaller stake will result in a much smaller profit on average, something like a $350$ fold increase with the large bet compared to $1.2$ increase with the small bet (i.e. you expect to have 24 dollars after 38 rounds with the small bet and 7000 dollars with the large bet).






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    it is if you consider that $q$ is chosen in a low risk manner and we aren't calculating it for $t>>k$, this isn't too bad an approximation. So it is probably overstating the profit from the large betting strategy.
    $endgroup$
    – probabilityislogic
    2 days ago










  • $begingroup$
    Your approach to maximize the median of $Z_t$ is actually the same as the approach from Dave Harris which is maximizing the mean of $Z_t$ (which is the same as the median of $Z_t$). It would be different when one is maximizing the mean of $Y_t$ which is lognormal distributed and for which the mean and median are not the same.
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    yesterday
















4












4








4





$begingroup$

I liked the answer given by Dave harris. just though I would come at the problem from a "low risk" perspective, rather than profit maximising



The random walk you are doing, assuming your fraction bet is $q$ and probability of winning $p=0.5$ has is given as
$$Y_t|Y_{t-1}=(1-q+3qX_t)Y_{t-1}$$
where $X_tsim Bernoulli(p)$. on average you have
$$E(Y_t|Y_{t-1}) = (1-q+3pq)Y_{t-1}$$
You can iteratively apply this to get
$$Y_t|Y_0=Y_0prod_{j=1}^t (1-q+3qX_t)$$
with expected value
$$E(Y_t|Y_{0}) = (1-q+3pq)^t Y_{0}$$
you can also express the amount at time $t$ as a function of a single random variable $Z_t=sum_{j=1}^t X_tsim Binomial(t,p)$, but noting that $Z_t$ is not independent from $Z_{t-1}$
$$Y_t|Y_0=Y_0 (1+2q)^{Z_t}(1-q)^{t-Z_t}$$



possible strategy



you could use this formula to determine a "low risk" value for $q$. Say assuming you wanted to ensure that after $k$ consecutive losses you still had half your original wealth. Then you set $q=1-2^{-k^{-1}}$



Taking the example $k=5$ means we set $q=0.129$, or with $k=15$ we set $q=0.045$.



Also, due to the recursive nature of the strategy, this risk is what you are taking every at every single bet. That is, at time $s$, by continuing to play you are ensuring that at time $k+s$ your wealth will be at least $0.5Y_{s}$



discussion



the above strategy does not depend on the pay off from winning, but rather about setting a boundary on losing. We can get the expected winnings by substituting in the value for $q$ we calculated, and at the time $k$ that was used with the risk in mind.



however, it is interesting to look at the median rather than expected pay off at time $t$, which can be found by assuming $median(Z_t)approx tp$.
$$Y_k|Y_0=Y_0 (1+2q)^{tp}(1-q)^{t(1-p)}$$
when $p=0.5$ the we have the ratio equal to $(1+q-2q^2)^{0.5t}$. This is maximised when $q=0.25$ and greater than $1$ when $q<0.5$



it is also interesting to calculate the chance you will be ahead at time $t$. to do this we need to determine the value $z$ such that
$$(1+2q)^{z}(1-q)^{t-z}>1$$
doing some rearranging we find that the proportion of wins should satisfy
$$frac{z}{t}>frac{log(1-q)}{log(1-q)-log(1+2q)}$$
This can be plugged into a normal approximation (note: mean of $0.5$ and standard error of $frac{0.5}{sqrt{t}}$) as
$$Pr(text{ahead at time t})approxPhileft(sqrt{t}frac{log(1+2q)+log(1-q)}{left[log(1+2q)-log(1-q)right]}right)$$



which clearly shows the game has very good odds. the factor multiplying $sqrt{t}$ is minimised when $q=0$ (maximised value of $frac{1}{3}$) and is monotonically decreasing as a function of $q$. so the "low risk" strategy is to bet a very small fraction of your wealth, and play a large number of times.



suppose we compare this with $q=frac{1}{3}$ and $q=frac{1}{100}$. the factor for each case is $0.11$ and $0.32$. This means after $38$ games you would have around a 95% chance to be ahead with the small bet, compared to a 75% chance with the larger bet. Additionally, you also have a chance of going broke with the larger bet, assuming you had to round your stake to the nearest 5 cents or dollar. Starting with $20$ this could go $13.35, 8.90,5.95,3.95,2.65,1.75,1.15,0.75,0.50,0.35,0.25,0.15,0.1,0.05,0$.
This is a sequence of $14$ losses out of $38$, and given the game would expect $19$ losses, if you get unlucky with the first few bets, then even winning may not make up for a bad streak (e.g., if most of your wins occur once most of the wealth is gone). going broke with the smaller 1% stake is not possible in $38$ games.
The flip side is that the smaller stake will result in a much smaller profit on average, something like a $350$ fold increase with the large bet compared to $1.2$ increase with the small bet (i.e. you expect to have 24 dollars after 38 rounds with the small bet and 7000 dollars with the large bet).






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$



I liked the answer given by Dave harris. just though I would come at the problem from a "low risk" perspective, rather than profit maximising



The random walk you are doing, assuming your fraction bet is $q$ and probability of winning $p=0.5$ has is given as
$$Y_t|Y_{t-1}=(1-q+3qX_t)Y_{t-1}$$
where $X_tsim Bernoulli(p)$. on average you have
$$E(Y_t|Y_{t-1}) = (1-q+3pq)Y_{t-1}$$
You can iteratively apply this to get
$$Y_t|Y_0=Y_0prod_{j=1}^t (1-q+3qX_t)$$
with expected value
$$E(Y_t|Y_{0}) = (1-q+3pq)^t Y_{0}$$
you can also express the amount at time $t$ as a function of a single random variable $Z_t=sum_{j=1}^t X_tsim Binomial(t,p)$, but noting that $Z_t$ is not independent from $Z_{t-1}$
$$Y_t|Y_0=Y_0 (1+2q)^{Z_t}(1-q)^{t-Z_t}$$



possible strategy



you could use this formula to determine a "low risk" value for $q$. Say assuming you wanted to ensure that after $k$ consecutive losses you still had half your original wealth. Then you set $q=1-2^{-k^{-1}}$



Taking the example $k=5$ means we set $q=0.129$, or with $k=15$ we set $q=0.045$.



Also, due to the recursive nature of the strategy, this risk is what you are taking every at every single bet. That is, at time $s$, by continuing to play you are ensuring that at time $k+s$ your wealth will be at least $0.5Y_{s}$



discussion



the above strategy does not depend on the pay off from winning, but rather about setting a boundary on losing. We can get the expected winnings by substituting in the value for $q$ we calculated, and at the time $k$ that was used with the risk in mind.



however, it is interesting to look at the median rather than expected pay off at time $t$, which can be found by assuming $median(Z_t)approx tp$.
$$Y_k|Y_0=Y_0 (1+2q)^{tp}(1-q)^{t(1-p)}$$
when $p=0.5$ the we have the ratio equal to $(1+q-2q^2)^{0.5t}$. This is maximised when $q=0.25$ and greater than $1$ when $q<0.5$



it is also interesting to calculate the chance you will be ahead at time $t$. to do this we need to determine the value $z$ such that
$$(1+2q)^{z}(1-q)^{t-z}>1$$
doing some rearranging we find that the proportion of wins should satisfy
$$frac{z}{t}>frac{log(1-q)}{log(1-q)-log(1+2q)}$$
This can be plugged into a normal approximation (note: mean of $0.5$ and standard error of $frac{0.5}{sqrt{t}}$) as
$$Pr(text{ahead at time t})approxPhileft(sqrt{t}frac{log(1+2q)+log(1-q)}{left[log(1+2q)-log(1-q)right]}right)$$



which clearly shows the game has very good odds. the factor multiplying $sqrt{t}$ is minimised when $q=0$ (maximised value of $frac{1}{3}$) and is monotonically decreasing as a function of $q$. so the "low risk" strategy is to bet a very small fraction of your wealth, and play a large number of times.



suppose we compare this with $q=frac{1}{3}$ and $q=frac{1}{100}$. the factor for each case is $0.11$ and $0.32$. This means after $38$ games you would have around a 95% chance to be ahead with the small bet, compared to a 75% chance with the larger bet. Additionally, you also have a chance of going broke with the larger bet, assuming you had to round your stake to the nearest 5 cents or dollar. Starting with $20$ this could go $13.35, 8.90,5.95,3.95,2.65,1.75,1.15,0.75,0.50,0.35,0.25,0.15,0.1,0.05,0$.
This is a sequence of $14$ losses out of $38$, and given the game would expect $19$ losses, if you get unlucky with the first few bets, then even winning may not make up for a bad streak (e.g., if most of your wins occur once most of the wealth is gone). going broke with the smaller 1% stake is not possible in $38$ games.
The flip side is that the smaller stake will result in a much smaller profit on average, something like a $350$ fold increase with the large bet compared to $1.2$ increase with the small bet (i.e. you expect to have 24 dollars after 38 rounds with the small bet and 7000 dollars with the large bet).







share|cite|improve this answer












share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer










answered 2 days ago









probabilityislogicprobabilityislogic

19.2k36385




19.2k36385












  • $begingroup$
    it is if you consider that $q$ is chosen in a low risk manner and we aren't calculating it for $t>>k$, this isn't too bad an approximation. So it is probably overstating the profit from the large betting strategy.
    $endgroup$
    – probabilityislogic
    2 days ago










  • $begingroup$
    Your approach to maximize the median of $Z_t$ is actually the same as the approach from Dave Harris which is maximizing the mean of $Z_t$ (which is the same as the median of $Z_t$). It would be different when one is maximizing the mean of $Y_t$ which is lognormal distributed and for which the mean and median are not the same.
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    yesterday




















  • $begingroup$
    it is if you consider that $q$ is chosen in a low risk manner and we aren't calculating it for $t>>k$, this isn't too bad an approximation. So it is probably overstating the profit from the large betting strategy.
    $endgroup$
    – probabilityislogic
    2 days ago










  • $begingroup$
    Your approach to maximize the median of $Z_t$ is actually the same as the approach from Dave Harris which is maximizing the mean of $Z_t$ (which is the same as the median of $Z_t$). It would be different when one is maximizing the mean of $Y_t$ which is lognormal distributed and for which the mean and median are not the same.
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    yesterday


















$begingroup$
it is if you consider that $q$ is chosen in a low risk manner and we aren't calculating it for $t>>k$, this isn't too bad an approximation. So it is probably overstating the profit from the large betting strategy.
$endgroup$
– probabilityislogic
2 days ago




$begingroup$
it is if you consider that $q$ is chosen in a low risk manner and we aren't calculating it for $t>>k$, this isn't too bad an approximation. So it is probably overstating the profit from the large betting strategy.
$endgroup$
– probabilityislogic
2 days ago












$begingroup$
Your approach to maximize the median of $Z_t$ is actually the same as the approach from Dave Harris which is maximizing the mean of $Z_t$ (which is the same as the median of $Z_t$). It would be different when one is maximizing the mean of $Y_t$ which is lognormal distributed and for which the mean and median are not the same.
$endgroup$
– Martijn Weterings
yesterday






$begingroup$
Your approach to maximize the median of $Z_t$ is actually the same as the approach from Dave Harris which is maximizing the mean of $Z_t$ (which is the same as the median of $Z_t$). It would be different when one is maximizing the mean of $Y_t$ which is lognormal distributed and for which the mean and median are not the same.
$endgroup$
– Martijn Weterings
yesterday













2












$begingroup$



Problem statement



Let $Y_t = log_{10}(M_t)$ be the logarithm of the amount of money $M_t$ the gambler has at time $t$.



Let $q$ be the fraction of money that the gambler is betting.



Let $Y_0 = 1$ be the amount of money that the gambler starts with (ten dollars). Let $Y_L=-2$ be the amount of money where the gambler goes bankrupt (below 1 cent). For simplicity we add a rule that the gambler stops gambling when he has passed some amount of money $Y_W$ (we can later lift this rule by taking the limit $Y_W to infty$).



Random walk



You can see the growth and decline of the money as an asymmetric random walk. That is you can describe $Y_t$ as:



$$Y_t = Y_0 + sum_{i=1}^t X_i$$



where



$$mathbb{P}[X_i= a_w =log(1+2q)] = mathbb{P}[X_i= a_l =log(1-q)] = frac{1}{2}$$



Probability of bankruptcy



Martingale



The expression



$$Z_t = c^{Y_t}$$



is a martingale when we choose $c$ such that.



$$c^{a_w}+ c^{a_l} = 2$$ (where $c<1$ if $q<0.5$). Since in that case



$$E[Z_{t+1}] = E[Z_t] frac{1}{2} c^{a_w} + E[Z_t] frac{1}{2} c^{a_l} = E[Z_t]$$



Probability to end up bankrupt



The stopping time (losing/bankruptcy $Y_t < Y_L$ or winning $Y_t>Y_W$) is almost surely finite since it requires in the worst case a winning streak (or losing streak) of a certain finite length, $frac{Y_W-Y_L}{a_w}$, which is almost surely gonna happen.



Then, we can use the optional stopping theorem to say $E[Z_tau]$ at the stopping time $tau$ equals the expected value $E[Z_0]$ at time zero.



Thus



$$c^{Y_0} = E[Z_0] = E[Z_tau] approx mathbb{P}[Y_tau<L] c^{Y_L} + (1-mathbb{P}[Y_tau<L]) c^{Y_W}$$



and



$$ mathbb{P}[Y_tau<Y_L] approx frac{c^{Y_0}-c^{Y_W}}{c^{Y_L}-c^{Y_W}}$$



and the limit $Y_W to infty$



$$ mathbb{P}[Y_tau<Y_L] approx c^{Y_0-Y_L}$$



Conclusions




Is there an optimal percentage of your cash you can offer without losing it all?




Whichever is the optimal percentage will depend on how you value different profits. However, we can say something about the probability to lose it all.



Only when the gambler is betting zero fraction of his money then he will certainly not go bankrupt.



With increasing $q$ the probability to go bankrupt will increase up to some point where the gambler will almost surely go bankrupt within a finite time (the gambler's ruin mentioned by Robert Long in the comments). This point, $q_{text{gambler's ruin}}$, is at $$q_{text{gambler's ruin}} = 1-1/b$$ This is the point where there is no solution for $c$ below one. This is also the point where the increasing steps $a_w$ are smaller than the decreasing steps $a_l$.



Thus, for $b=2$, as long as the gambler bets less than half the money then the gambler will not certainly go bankrupt.




do the odds of losing all your money decrease or increase over time?




The probability to go bankrupt is dependent on the distance from the amount of money where the gambler goes bankrupt. When $q<q_{text{gambler's ruin}}$ the gambler's money will, on average increase, and the probability to go bankrupt will, on average, decrease.



Bankruptcy probability when using the Kelly criterion.



When you use the Kelly criterion mentioned in Dave Harris answer, $q = 0.5(1-1/b)$, for $b$ being the ratio between loss and profit in a single bet, then independent from $b$ the value of $c$ will be equal to $0.1$ and the probability to go bankrupt will be $0.1^{S-L}$.



That is, independent from the assymetry parameter $b$ of the magic tree, the probability to go bankrupt, when using the Kelly criterion, is equal to the ratio of the amount of money where the gambler goes bankrupt and the amount of money that the gambler starts with. For ten dollars and 1 cent this is a 1:1000 probability to go bankrupt, when using the Kelly criterion.



Simulations



The simulations below show different simulated trajectories for different gambling strategies. The red trajectories are ones that ended up bankrupt (hit the line $Y_t=-2$).



simulations



Distribution of profits after time $t$



To further illustrate the possible outcomes of gambling with the money tree, you can model the distribution of $Y_t$ as a one dimensional diffusion process in a homogeneous force field and with an absorbing boundary (where the gambler get's bankrupt). The solution for this situation has been given by Smoluchowski




Smoluchowski, Marian V. "Über Brownsche Molekularbewegung unter Einwirkung äußerer Kräfte und deren Zusammenhang mit der verallgemeinerten Diffusionsgleichung." Annalen der Physik 353.24 (1916): 1103-1112. (online available via: https://www.physik.uni-augsburg.de/theo1/hanggi/History/BM-History.html)



Equation 8:



$$ W(x_0,x,t) = frac{e^{-frac{c(x-x_0)}{2D} - frac{c^2 t}{4D}}}{2 sqrt{pi D t}} left[ e^{-frac{(x-x_0)^2}{4Dt}} - e^{-frac{(x+x_0)^2}{4Dt}} right]$$




This diffusion equation relates to the tree problem when we set the speed $c$ equal to the expected increase $E[Y_t]$, we set $D$ equal to the variance of the change in a single steps $text{Var}(X_t)$, $x_0$ is the initial amount of money, and $t$ is the number of steps.



The image and code below demonstrate the equation:




  • The histogram shows the result from a simulation.


  • The dotted line shows a model when we use a naive normal distribution to approximate the distribution (this corresponds to the absence of the absorbing 'bankruptcy' barrier). This is wrong because some of the results above the bankruptcy level involve trajectories that have passed the bankruptcy level at an earlier time.


  • The continuous line is the approximation using the formula by Smoluchowski.



illustration as diffusion in force field



Codes



#
## Simulations of random walks and bankruptcy:
#

# functions to compute c
cx = function(c,x) {
c^log(1-x,10)+c^log(1+2*x,10) - 2
}
findc = function(x) {
r <- uniroot(cx, c(0,1-0.1^10),x=x,tol=10^-130)
r$root
}


# settings
set.seed(1)
n <- 100000
n2 <- 1000
q <- 0.45

# repeating different betting strategies
for (q in c(0.35,0.4,0.45)) {
# plot empty canvas
plot(1,-1000,
xlim=c(0,n2),ylim=c(-2,50),
type="l",
xlab = "time step", ylab = expression(log[10](M[t])) )

# steps in the logarithm of the money
steps <- c(log(1+2*q,10),log(1-q,10))

# counter for number of bankrupts
bank <- 0

# computing 1000 times
for (i in 1:1000) {
# sampling wins or looses
X_t <- sample(steps, n, replace = TRUE)
# compute log of money
Y_t <- 1+cumsum(X_t)
# compute money
M_t <- 10^Y_t
# optional stopping (bankruptcy)
tau <- min(c(n,which(-2 > Y_t)))
if (tau<n) {
bank <- bank+1
}
# plot only 100 to prevent clutter
if (i<=100) {
col=rgb(tau<n,0,0,0.5)
lines(1:tau,Y_t[1:tau],col=col)
}
}
text(0,45,paste0(bank, " bankruptcies out of 1000 n", "theoretic bankruptcy rate is ", round(findc(q)^3,4)),cex=1,pos=4)
title(paste0("betting a fraction ", round(q,2)))
}

#
## Simulation of histogram of profits/results
#

# settings
set.seed(1)
rep <- 10000 # repetitions for histogram
n <- 5000 # time steps
q <- 0.45 # betting fraction
b <- 2 # betting ratio loss/profit
x0 <- 3 # starting money

# steps in the logarithm of the money
steps <- c(log(1+b*q,10),log(1-q,10))

# to prevent Moiré pattern in
# set binsize to discrete differences in results
binsize <- 2*(steps[1]-steps[2])

for (n in c(200,500,1000)) {

# computing several trials
pays <- rep(0,rep)
for (i in 1:rep) {
# sampling wins or looses
X_t <- sample(steps, n, replace = TRUE)
# you could also make steps according to a normal distribution
# this will give a smoother histogram
# to do this uncomment the line below
# X_t <- rnorm(n,mean(steps),sqrt(0.25*(steps[1]-steps[2])^2))

# compute log of money
Y_t <- x0+cumsum(X_t)
# compute money
M_t <- 10^Y_t
# optional stopping (bankruptcy)
tau <- min(c(n,which(Y_t < 0)))
if (tau<n) {
Y_t[n] <- 0
M_t[n] <- 0
}
pays[i] <- Y_t[n]
}

# histogram
h <- hist(pays[pays>0],
breaks = seq(0,round(2+max(pays)),binsize),
col=rgb(0,0,0,0.5),
ylim=c(0,1200),
xlab = "log(result)", ylab = "counts",
main = "")
title(paste0("after ", n ," steps"),line = 0)

# regular diffusion in a force field (shifted normal distribution)
x <- h$mids
mu <- x0+n*mean(steps)
sig <- sqrt(n*0.25*(steps[1]-steps[2])^2)
lines(x,rep*binsize*(dnorm(x,mu,sig)), lty=2)

# diffusion using the solution by Smoluchowski
# which accounts for absorption
lines(x,rep*binsize*Smoluchowski(x,x0,0.25*(steps[1]-steps[2])^2,mean(steps),n))

}





share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    "That is, independent from the assymetry parameter b of the magic tree, the probability to go bankrupt, when using the Kelly criterion, is equal to the ratio of the amount of money where the gambler goes bankrupt and the amount of money that the gambler starts with. For ten dollars and 1 cent this is a 1:1000 probability to go bankrupt" Im a bit surprised about this. So this means the probability to go bankrupt will be 1:1000 even if the payout is 10 times the offered money per round? How is this possible when the odds of going bankrupt decrease as your money grows?
    $endgroup$
    – ElectronicToothpick
    17 hours ago






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    @ElectronicToothpick If the payout is larger, and if you do not change the fraction that you gamble, then the probability to go bankrupt will be smaller. However, when you increase the fraction that you gamble, then this may not be true anymore. With the Kelly criterion, you will increase the fraction to gamble when the payout is higher. This will increase the expected value of the logarithm of the money, but as a consequence, the probability to go bankrupt will remain the same.
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    14 hours ago








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Actually, when the gambler is not using the Kelly criterion, which optimizes $E[log M_t]$, but instead chooses to optimize $E[M_t]$, then the consequence is that a higher fraction of the amount of money is being gambled. Possibly this might lead to an increase in the risk of bankruptcy when the payout is made larger. I could add an analysis of this, but I am afraid that my answer is already too long and/or complex.
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    14 hours ago


















2












$begingroup$



Problem statement



Let $Y_t = log_{10}(M_t)$ be the logarithm of the amount of money $M_t$ the gambler has at time $t$.



Let $q$ be the fraction of money that the gambler is betting.



Let $Y_0 = 1$ be the amount of money that the gambler starts with (ten dollars). Let $Y_L=-2$ be the amount of money where the gambler goes bankrupt (below 1 cent). For simplicity we add a rule that the gambler stops gambling when he has passed some amount of money $Y_W$ (we can later lift this rule by taking the limit $Y_W to infty$).



Random walk



You can see the growth and decline of the money as an asymmetric random walk. That is you can describe $Y_t$ as:



$$Y_t = Y_0 + sum_{i=1}^t X_i$$



where



$$mathbb{P}[X_i= a_w =log(1+2q)] = mathbb{P}[X_i= a_l =log(1-q)] = frac{1}{2}$$



Probability of bankruptcy



Martingale



The expression



$$Z_t = c^{Y_t}$$



is a martingale when we choose $c$ such that.



$$c^{a_w}+ c^{a_l} = 2$$ (where $c<1$ if $q<0.5$). Since in that case



$$E[Z_{t+1}] = E[Z_t] frac{1}{2} c^{a_w} + E[Z_t] frac{1}{2} c^{a_l} = E[Z_t]$$



Probability to end up bankrupt



The stopping time (losing/bankruptcy $Y_t < Y_L$ or winning $Y_t>Y_W$) is almost surely finite since it requires in the worst case a winning streak (or losing streak) of a certain finite length, $frac{Y_W-Y_L}{a_w}$, which is almost surely gonna happen.



Then, we can use the optional stopping theorem to say $E[Z_tau]$ at the stopping time $tau$ equals the expected value $E[Z_0]$ at time zero.



Thus



$$c^{Y_0} = E[Z_0] = E[Z_tau] approx mathbb{P}[Y_tau<L] c^{Y_L} + (1-mathbb{P}[Y_tau<L]) c^{Y_W}$$



and



$$ mathbb{P}[Y_tau<Y_L] approx frac{c^{Y_0}-c^{Y_W}}{c^{Y_L}-c^{Y_W}}$$



and the limit $Y_W to infty$



$$ mathbb{P}[Y_tau<Y_L] approx c^{Y_0-Y_L}$$



Conclusions




Is there an optimal percentage of your cash you can offer without losing it all?




Whichever is the optimal percentage will depend on how you value different profits. However, we can say something about the probability to lose it all.



Only when the gambler is betting zero fraction of his money then he will certainly not go bankrupt.



With increasing $q$ the probability to go bankrupt will increase up to some point where the gambler will almost surely go bankrupt within a finite time (the gambler's ruin mentioned by Robert Long in the comments). This point, $q_{text{gambler's ruin}}$, is at $$q_{text{gambler's ruin}} = 1-1/b$$ This is the point where there is no solution for $c$ below one. This is also the point where the increasing steps $a_w$ are smaller than the decreasing steps $a_l$.



Thus, for $b=2$, as long as the gambler bets less than half the money then the gambler will not certainly go bankrupt.




do the odds of losing all your money decrease or increase over time?




The probability to go bankrupt is dependent on the distance from the amount of money where the gambler goes bankrupt. When $q<q_{text{gambler's ruin}}$ the gambler's money will, on average increase, and the probability to go bankrupt will, on average, decrease.



Bankruptcy probability when using the Kelly criterion.



When you use the Kelly criterion mentioned in Dave Harris answer, $q = 0.5(1-1/b)$, for $b$ being the ratio between loss and profit in a single bet, then independent from $b$ the value of $c$ will be equal to $0.1$ and the probability to go bankrupt will be $0.1^{S-L}$.



That is, independent from the assymetry parameter $b$ of the magic tree, the probability to go bankrupt, when using the Kelly criterion, is equal to the ratio of the amount of money where the gambler goes bankrupt and the amount of money that the gambler starts with. For ten dollars and 1 cent this is a 1:1000 probability to go bankrupt, when using the Kelly criterion.



Simulations



The simulations below show different simulated trajectories for different gambling strategies. The red trajectories are ones that ended up bankrupt (hit the line $Y_t=-2$).



simulations



Distribution of profits after time $t$



To further illustrate the possible outcomes of gambling with the money tree, you can model the distribution of $Y_t$ as a one dimensional diffusion process in a homogeneous force field and with an absorbing boundary (where the gambler get's bankrupt). The solution for this situation has been given by Smoluchowski




Smoluchowski, Marian V. "Über Brownsche Molekularbewegung unter Einwirkung äußerer Kräfte und deren Zusammenhang mit der verallgemeinerten Diffusionsgleichung." Annalen der Physik 353.24 (1916): 1103-1112. (online available via: https://www.physik.uni-augsburg.de/theo1/hanggi/History/BM-History.html)



Equation 8:



$$ W(x_0,x,t) = frac{e^{-frac{c(x-x_0)}{2D} - frac{c^2 t}{4D}}}{2 sqrt{pi D t}} left[ e^{-frac{(x-x_0)^2}{4Dt}} - e^{-frac{(x+x_0)^2}{4Dt}} right]$$




This diffusion equation relates to the tree problem when we set the speed $c$ equal to the expected increase $E[Y_t]$, we set $D$ equal to the variance of the change in a single steps $text{Var}(X_t)$, $x_0$ is the initial amount of money, and $t$ is the number of steps.



The image and code below demonstrate the equation:




  • The histogram shows the result from a simulation.


  • The dotted line shows a model when we use a naive normal distribution to approximate the distribution (this corresponds to the absence of the absorbing 'bankruptcy' barrier). This is wrong because some of the results above the bankruptcy level involve trajectories that have passed the bankruptcy level at an earlier time.


  • The continuous line is the approximation using the formula by Smoluchowski.



illustration as diffusion in force field



Codes



#
## Simulations of random walks and bankruptcy:
#

# functions to compute c
cx = function(c,x) {
c^log(1-x,10)+c^log(1+2*x,10) - 2
}
findc = function(x) {
r <- uniroot(cx, c(0,1-0.1^10),x=x,tol=10^-130)
r$root
}


# settings
set.seed(1)
n <- 100000
n2 <- 1000
q <- 0.45

# repeating different betting strategies
for (q in c(0.35,0.4,0.45)) {
# plot empty canvas
plot(1,-1000,
xlim=c(0,n2),ylim=c(-2,50),
type="l",
xlab = "time step", ylab = expression(log[10](M[t])) )

# steps in the logarithm of the money
steps <- c(log(1+2*q,10),log(1-q,10))

# counter for number of bankrupts
bank <- 0

# computing 1000 times
for (i in 1:1000) {
# sampling wins or looses
X_t <- sample(steps, n, replace = TRUE)
# compute log of money
Y_t <- 1+cumsum(X_t)
# compute money
M_t <- 10^Y_t
# optional stopping (bankruptcy)
tau <- min(c(n,which(-2 > Y_t)))
if (tau<n) {
bank <- bank+1
}
# plot only 100 to prevent clutter
if (i<=100) {
col=rgb(tau<n,0,0,0.5)
lines(1:tau,Y_t[1:tau],col=col)
}
}
text(0,45,paste0(bank, " bankruptcies out of 1000 n", "theoretic bankruptcy rate is ", round(findc(q)^3,4)),cex=1,pos=4)
title(paste0("betting a fraction ", round(q,2)))
}

#
## Simulation of histogram of profits/results
#

# settings
set.seed(1)
rep <- 10000 # repetitions for histogram
n <- 5000 # time steps
q <- 0.45 # betting fraction
b <- 2 # betting ratio loss/profit
x0 <- 3 # starting money

# steps in the logarithm of the money
steps <- c(log(1+b*q,10),log(1-q,10))

# to prevent Moiré pattern in
# set binsize to discrete differences in results
binsize <- 2*(steps[1]-steps[2])

for (n in c(200,500,1000)) {

# computing several trials
pays <- rep(0,rep)
for (i in 1:rep) {
# sampling wins or looses
X_t <- sample(steps, n, replace = TRUE)
# you could also make steps according to a normal distribution
# this will give a smoother histogram
# to do this uncomment the line below
# X_t <- rnorm(n,mean(steps),sqrt(0.25*(steps[1]-steps[2])^2))

# compute log of money
Y_t <- x0+cumsum(X_t)
# compute money
M_t <- 10^Y_t
# optional stopping (bankruptcy)
tau <- min(c(n,which(Y_t < 0)))
if (tau<n) {
Y_t[n] <- 0
M_t[n] <- 0
}
pays[i] <- Y_t[n]
}

# histogram
h <- hist(pays[pays>0],
breaks = seq(0,round(2+max(pays)),binsize),
col=rgb(0,0,0,0.5),
ylim=c(0,1200),
xlab = "log(result)", ylab = "counts",
main = "")
title(paste0("after ", n ," steps"),line = 0)

# regular diffusion in a force field (shifted normal distribution)
x <- h$mids
mu <- x0+n*mean(steps)
sig <- sqrt(n*0.25*(steps[1]-steps[2])^2)
lines(x,rep*binsize*(dnorm(x,mu,sig)), lty=2)

# diffusion using the solution by Smoluchowski
# which accounts for absorption
lines(x,rep*binsize*Smoluchowski(x,x0,0.25*(steps[1]-steps[2])^2,mean(steps),n))

}





share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    "That is, independent from the assymetry parameter b of the magic tree, the probability to go bankrupt, when using the Kelly criterion, is equal to the ratio of the amount of money where the gambler goes bankrupt and the amount of money that the gambler starts with. For ten dollars and 1 cent this is a 1:1000 probability to go bankrupt" Im a bit surprised about this. So this means the probability to go bankrupt will be 1:1000 even if the payout is 10 times the offered money per round? How is this possible when the odds of going bankrupt decrease as your money grows?
    $endgroup$
    – ElectronicToothpick
    17 hours ago






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    @ElectronicToothpick If the payout is larger, and if you do not change the fraction that you gamble, then the probability to go bankrupt will be smaller. However, when you increase the fraction that you gamble, then this may not be true anymore. With the Kelly criterion, you will increase the fraction to gamble when the payout is higher. This will increase the expected value of the logarithm of the money, but as a consequence, the probability to go bankrupt will remain the same.
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    14 hours ago








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Actually, when the gambler is not using the Kelly criterion, which optimizes $E[log M_t]$, but instead chooses to optimize $E[M_t]$, then the consequence is that a higher fraction of the amount of money is being gambled. Possibly this might lead to an increase in the risk of bankruptcy when the payout is made larger. I could add an analysis of this, but I am afraid that my answer is already too long and/or complex.
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    14 hours ago
















2












2








2





$begingroup$



Problem statement



Let $Y_t = log_{10}(M_t)$ be the logarithm of the amount of money $M_t$ the gambler has at time $t$.



Let $q$ be the fraction of money that the gambler is betting.



Let $Y_0 = 1$ be the amount of money that the gambler starts with (ten dollars). Let $Y_L=-2$ be the amount of money where the gambler goes bankrupt (below 1 cent). For simplicity we add a rule that the gambler stops gambling when he has passed some amount of money $Y_W$ (we can later lift this rule by taking the limit $Y_W to infty$).



Random walk



You can see the growth and decline of the money as an asymmetric random walk. That is you can describe $Y_t$ as:



$$Y_t = Y_0 + sum_{i=1}^t X_i$$



where



$$mathbb{P}[X_i= a_w =log(1+2q)] = mathbb{P}[X_i= a_l =log(1-q)] = frac{1}{2}$$



Probability of bankruptcy



Martingale



The expression



$$Z_t = c^{Y_t}$$



is a martingale when we choose $c$ such that.



$$c^{a_w}+ c^{a_l} = 2$$ (where $c<1$ if $q<0.5$). Since in that case



$$E[Z_{t+1}] = E[Z_t] frac{1}{2} c^{a_w} + E[Z_t] frac{1}{2} c^{a_l} = E[Z_t]$$



Probability to end up bankrupt



The stopping time (losing/bankruptcy $Y_t < Y_L$ or winning $Y_t>Y_W$) is almost surely finite since it requires in the worst case a winning streak (or losing streak) of a certain finite length, $frac{Y_W-Y_L}{a_w}$, which is almost surely gonna happen.



Then, we can use the optional stopping theorem to say $E[Z_tau]$ at the stopping time $tau$ equals the expected value $E[Z_0]$ at time zero.



Thus



$$c^{Y_0} = E[Z_0] = E[Z_tau] approx mathbb{P}[Y_tau<L] c^{Y_L} + (1-mathbb{P}[Y_tau<L]) c^{Y_W}$$



and



$$ mathbb{P}[Y_tau<Y_L] approx frac{c^{Y_0}-c^{Y_W}}{c^{Y_L}-c^{Y_W}}$$



and the limit $Y_W to infty$



$$ mathbb{P}[Y_tau<Y_L] approx c^{Y_0-Y_L}$$



Conclusions




Is there an optimal percentage of your cash you can offer without losing it all?




Whichever is the optimal percentage will depend on how you value different profits. However, we can say something about the probability to lose it all.



Only when the gambler is betting zero fraction of his money then he will certainly not go bankrupt.



With increasing $q$ the probability to go bankrupt will increase up to some point where the gambler will almost surely go bankrupt within a finite time (the gambler's ruin mentioned by Robert Long in the comments). This point, $q_{text{gambler's ruin}}$, is at $$q_{text{gambler's ruin}} = 1-1/b$$ This is the point where there is no solution for $c$ below one. This is also the point where the increasing steps $a_w$ are smaller than the decreasing steps $a_l$.



Thus, for $b=2$, as long as the gambler bets less than half the money then the gambler will not certainly go bankrupt.




do the odds of losing all your money decrease or increase over time?




The probability to go bankrupt is dependent on the distance from the amount of money where the gambler goes bankrupt. When $q<q_{text{gambler's ruin}}$ the gambler's money will, on average increase, and the probability to go bankrupt will, on average, decrease.



Bankruptcy probability when using the Kelly criterion.



When you use the Kelly criterion mentioned in Dave Harris answer, $q = 0.5(1-1/b)$, for $b$ being the ratio between loss and profit in a single bet, then independent from $b$ the value of $c$ will be equal to $0.1$ and the probability to go bankrupt will be $0.1^{S-L}$.



That is, independent from the assymetry parameter $b$ of the magic tree, the probability to go bankrupt, when using the Kelly criterion, is equal to the ratio of the amount of money where the gambler goes bankrupt and the amount of money that the gambler starts with. For ten dollars and 1 cent this is a 1:1000 probability to go bankrupt, when using the Kelly criterion.



Simulations



The simulations below show different simulated trajectories for different gambling strategies. The red trajectories are ones that ended up bankrupt (hit the line $Y_t=-2$).



simulations



Distribution of profits after time $t$



To further illustrate the possible outcomes of gambling with the money tree, you can model the distribution of $Y_t$ as a one dimensional diffusion process in a homogeneous force field and with an absorbing boundary (where the gambler get's bankrupt). The solution for this situation has been given by Smoluchowski




Smoluchowski, Marian V. "Über Brownsche Molekularbewegung unter Einwirkung äußerer Kräfte und deren Zusammenhang mit der verallgemeinerten Diffusionsgleichung." Annalen der Physik 353.24 (1916): 1103-1112. (online available via: https://www.physik.uni-augsburg.de/theo1/hanggi/History/BM-History.html)



Equation 8:



$$ W(x_0,x,t) = frac{e^{-frac{c(x-x_0)}{2D} - frac{c^2 t}{4D}}}{2 sqrt{pi D t}} left[ e^{-frac{(x-x_0)^2}{4Dt}} - e^{-frac{(x+x_0)^2}{4Dt}} right]$$




This diffusion equation relates to the tree problem when we set the speed $c$ equal to the expected increase $E[Y_t]$, we set $D$ equal to the variance of the change in a single steps $text{Var}(X_t)$, $x_0$ is the initial amount of money, and $t$ is the number of steps.



The image and code below demonstrate the equation:




  • The histogram shows the result from a simulation.


  • The dotted line shows a model when we use a naive normal distribution to approximate the distribution (this corresponds to the absence of the absorbing 'bankruptcy' barrier). This is wrong because some of the results above the bankruptcy level involve trajectories that have passed the bankruptcy level at an earlier time.


  • The continuous line is the approximation using the formula by Smoluchowski.



illustration as diffusion in force field



Codes



#
## Simulations of random walks and bankruptcy:
#

# functions to compute c
cx = function(c,x) {
c^log(1-x,10)+c^log(1+2*x,10) - 2
}
findc = function(x) {
r <- uniroot(cx, c(0,1-0.1^10),x=x,tol=10^-130)
r$root
}


# settings
set.seed(1)
n <- 100000
n2 <- 1000
q <- 0.45

# repeating different betting strategies
for (q in c(0.35,0.4,0.45)) {
# plot empty canvas
plot(1,-1000,
xlim=c(0,n2),ylim=c(-2,50),
type="l",
xlab = "time step", ylab = expression(log[10](M[t])) )

# steps in the logarithm of the money
steps <- c(log(1+2*q,10),log(1-q,10))

# counter for number of bankrupts
bank <- 0

# computing 1000 times
for (i in 1:1000) {
# sampling wins or looses
X_t <- sample(steps, n, replace = TRUE)
# compute log of money
Y_t <- 1+cumsum(X_t)
# compute money
M_t <- 10^Y_t
# optional stopping (bankruptcy)
tau <- min(c(n,which(-2 > Y_t)))
if (tau<n) {
bank <- bank+1
}
# plot only 100 to prevent clutter
if (i<=100) {
col=rgb(tau<n,0,0,0.5)
lines(1:tau,Y_t[1:tau],col=col)
}
}
text(0,45,paste0(bank, " bankruptcies out of 1000 n", "theoretic bankruptcy rate is ", round(findc(q)^3,4)),cex=1,pos=4)
title(paste0("betting a fraction ", round(q,2)))
}

#
## Simulation of histogram of profits/results
#

# settings
set.seed(1)
rep <- 10000 # repetitions for histogram
n <- 5000 # time steps
q <- 0.45 # betting fraction
b <- 2 # betting ratio loss/profit
x0 <- 3 # starting money

# steps in the logarithm of the money
steps <- c(log(1+b*q,10),log(1-q,10))

# to prevent Moiré pattern in
# set binsize to discrete differences in results
binsize <- 2*(steps[1]-steps[2])

for (n in c(200,500,1000)) {

# computing several trials
pays <- rep(0,rep)
for (i in 1:rep) {
# sampling wins or looses
X_t <- sample(steps, n, replace = TRUE)
# you could also make steps according to a normal distribution
# this will give a smoother histogram
# to do this uncomment the line below
# X_t <- rnorm(n,mean(steps),sqrt(0.25*(steps[1]-steps[2])^2))

# compute log of money
Y_t <- x0+cumsum(X_t)
# compute money
M_t <- 10^Y_t
# optional stopping (bankruptcy)
tau <- min(c(n,which(Y_t < 0)))
if (tau<n) {
Y_t[n] <- 0
M_t[n] <- 0
}
pays[i] <- Y_t[n]
}

# histogram
h <- hist(pays[pays>0],
breaks = seq(0,round(2+max(pays)),binsize),
col=rgb(0,0,0,0.5),
ylim=c(0,1200),
xlab = "log(result)", ylab = "counts",
main = "")
title(paste0("after ", n ," steps"),line = 0)

# regular diffusion in a force field (shifted normal distribution)
x <- h$mids
mu <- x0+n*mean(steps)
sig <- sqrt(n*0.25*(steps[1]-steps[2])^2)
lines(x,rep*binsize*(dnorm(x,mu,sig)), lty=2)

# diffusion using the solution by Smoluchowski
# which accounts for absorption
lines(x,rep*binsize*Smoluchowski(x,x0,0.25*(steps[1]-steps[2])^2,mean(steps),n))

}





share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$





Problem statement



Let $Y_t = log_{10}(M_t)$ be the logarithm of the amount of money $M_t$ the gambler has at time $t$.



Let $q$ be the fraction of money that the gambler is betting.



Let $Y_0 = 1$ be the amount of money that the gambler starts with (ten dollars). Let $Y_L=-2$ be the amount of money where the gambler goes bankrupt (below 1 cent). For simplicity we add a rule that the gambler stops gambling when he has passed some amount of money $Y_W$ (we can later lift this rule by taking the limit $Y_W to infty$).



Random walk



You can see the growth and decline of the money as an asymmetric random walk. That is you can describe $Y_t$ as:



$$Y_t = Y_0 + sum_{i=1}^t X_i$$



where



$$mathbb{P}[X_i= a_w =log(1+2q)] = mathbb{P}[X_i= a_l =log(1-q)] = frac{1}{2}$$



Probability of bankruptcy



Martingale



The expression



$$Z_t = c^{Y_t}$$



is a martingale when we choose $c$ such that.



$$c^{a_w}+ c^{a_l} = 2$$ (where $c<1$ if $q<0.5$). Since in that case



$$E[Z_{t+1}] = E[Z_t] frac{1}{2} c^{a_w} + E[Z_t] frac{1}{2} c^{a_l} = E[Z_t]$$



Probability to end up bankrupt



The stopping time (losing/bankruptcy $Y_t < Y_L$ or winning $Y_t>Y_W$) is almost surely finite since it requires in the worst case a winning streak (or losing streak) of a certain finite length, $frac{Y_W-Y_L}{a_w}$, which is almost surely gonna happen.



Then, we can use the optional stopping theorem to say $E[Z_tau]$ at the stopping time $tau$ equals the expected value $E[Z_0]$ at time zero.



Thus



$$c^{Y_0} = E[Z_0] = E[Z_tau] approx mathbb{P}[Y_tau<L] c^{Y_L} + (1-mathbb{P}[Y_tau<L]) c^{Y_W}$$



and



$$ mathbb{P}[Y_tau<Y_L] approx frac{c^{Y_0}-c^{Y_W}}{c^{Y_L}-c^{Y_W}}$$



and the limit $Y_W to infty$



$$ mathbb{P}[Y_tau<Y_L] approx c^{Y_0-Y_L}$$



Conclusions




Is there an optimal percentage of your cash you can offer without losing it all?




Whichever is the optimal percentage will depend on how you value different profits. However, we can say something about the probability to lose it all.



Only when the gambler is betting zero fraction of his money then he will certainly not go bankrupt.



With increasing $q$ the probability to go bankrupt will increase up to some point where the gambler will almost surely go bankrupt within a finite time (the gambler's ruin mentioned by Robert Long in the comments). This point, $q_{text{gambler's ruin}}$, is at $$q_{text{gambler's ruin}} = 1-1/b$$ This is the point where there is no solution for $c$ below one. This is also the point where the increasing steps $a_w$ are smaller than the decreasing steps $a_l$.



Thus, for $b=2$, as long as the gambler bets less than half the money then the gambler will not certainly go bankrupt.




do the odds of losing all your money decrease or increase over time?




The probability to go bankrupt is dependent on the distance from the amount of money where the gambler goes bankrupt. When $q<q_{text{gambler's ruin}}$ the gambler's money will, on average increase, and the probability to go bankrupt will, on average, decrease.



Bankruptcy probability when using the Kelly criterion.



When you use the Kelly criterion mentioned in Dave Harris answer, $q = 0.5(1-1/b)$, for $b$ being the ratio between loss and profit in a single bet, then independent from $b$ the value of $c$ will be equal to $0.1$ and the probability to go bankrupt will be $0.1^{S-L}$.



That is, independent from the assymetry parameter $b$ of the magic tree, the probability to go bankrupt, when using the Kelly criterion, is equal to the ratio of the amount of money where the gambler goes bankrupt and the amount of money that the gambler starts with. For ten dollars and 1 cent this is a 1:1000 probability to go bankrupt, when using the Kelly criterion.



Simulations



The simulations below show different simulated trajectories for different gambling strategies. The red trajectories are ones that ended up bankrupt (hit the line $Y_t=-2$).



simulations



Distribution of profits after time $t$



To further illustrate the possible outcomes of gambling with the money tree, you can model the distribution of $Y_t$ as a one dimensional diffusion process in a homogeneous force field and with an absorbing boundary (where the gambler get's bankrupt). The solution for this situation has been given by Smoluchowski




Smoluchowski, Marian V. "Über Brownsche Molekularbewegung unter Einwirkung äußerer Kräfte und deren Zusammenhang mit der verallgemeinerten Diffusionsgleichung." Annalen der Physik 353.24 (1916): 1103-1112. (online available via: https://www.physik.uni-augsburg.de/theo1/hanggi/History/BM-History.html)



Equation 8:



$$ W(x_0,x,t) = frac{e^{-frac{c(x-x_0)}{2D} - frac{c^2 t}{4D}}}{2 sqrt{pi D t}} left[ e^{-frac{(x-x_0)^2}{4Dt}} - e^{-frac{(x+x_0)^2}{4Dt}} right]$$




This diffusion equation relates to the tree problem when we set the speed $c$ equal to the expected increase $E[Y_t]$, we set $D$ equal to the variance of the change in a single steps $text{Var}(X_t)$, $x_0$ is the initial amount of money, and $t$ is the number of steps.



The image and code below demonstrate the equation:




  • The histogram shows the result from a simulation.


  • The dotted line shows a model when we use a naive normal distribution to approximate the distribution (this corresponds to the absence of the absorbing 'bankruptcy' barrier). This is wrong because some of the results above the bankruptcy level involve trajectories that have passed the bankruptcy level at an earlier time.


  • The continuous line is the approximation using the formula by Smoluchowski.



illustration as diffusion in force field



Codes



#
## Simulations of random walks and bankruptcy:
#

# functions to compute c
cx = function(c,x) {
c^log(1-x,10)+c^log(1+2*x,10) - 2
}
findc = function(x) {
r <- uniroot(cx, c(0,1-0.1^10),x=x,tol=10^-130)
r$root
}


# settings
set.seed(1)
n <- 100000
n2 <- 1000
q <- 0.45

# repeating different betting strategies
for (q in c(0.35,0.4,0.45)) {
# plot empty canvas
plot(1,-1000,
xlim=c(0,n2),ylim=c(-2,50),
type="l",
xlab = "time step", ylab = expression(log[10](M[t])) )

# steps in the logarithm of the money
steps <- c(log(1+2*q,10),log(1-q,10))

# counter for number of bankrupts
bank <- 0

# computing 1000 times
for (i in 1:1000) {
# sampling wins or looses
X_t <- sample(steps, n, replace = TRUE)
# compute log of money
Y_t <- 1+cumsum(X_t)
# compute money
M_t <- 10^Y_t
# optional stopping (bankruptcy)
tau <- min(c(n,which(-2 > Y_t)))
if (tau<n) {
bank <- bank+1
}
# plot only 100 to prevent clutter
if (i<=100) {
col=rgb(tau<n,0,0,0.5)
lines(1:tau,Y_t[1:tau],col=col)
}
}
text(0,45,paste0(bank, " bankruptcies out of 1000 n", "theoretic bankruptcy rate is ", round(findc(q)^3,4)),cex=1,pos=4)
title(paste0("betting a fraction ", round(q,2)))
}

#
## Simulation of histogram of profits/results
#

# settings
set.seed(1)
rep <- 10000 # repetitions for histogram
n <- 5000 # time steps
q <- 0.45 # betting fraction
b <- 2 # betting ratio loss/profit
x0 <- 3 # starting money

# steps in the logarithm of the money
steps <- c(log(1+b*q,10),log(1-q,10))

# to prevent Moiré pattern in
# set binsize to discrete differences in results
binsize <- 2*(steps[1]-steps[2])

for (n in c(200,500,1000)) {

# computing several trials
pays <- rep(0,rep)
for (i in 1:rep) {
# sampling wins or looses
X_t <- sample(steps, n, replace = TRUE)
# you could also make steps according to a normal distribution
# this will give a smoother histogram
# to do this uncomment the line below
# X_t <- rnorm(n,mean(steps),sqrt(0.25*(steps[1]-steps[2])^2))

# compute log of money
Y_t <- x0+cumsum(X_t)
# compute money
M_t <- 10^Y_t
# optional stopping (bankruptcy)
tau <- min(c(n,which(Y_t < 0)))
if (tau<n) {
Y_t[n] <- 0
M_t[n] <- 0
}
pays[i] <- Y_t[n]
}

# histogram
h <- hist(pays[pays>0],
breaks = seq(0,round(2+max(pays)),binsize),
col=rgb(0,0,0,0.5),
ylim=c(0,1200),
xlab = "log(result)", ylab = "counts",
main = "")
title(paste0("after ", n ," steps"),line = 0)

# regular diffusion in a force field (shifted normal distribution)
x <- h$mids
mu <- x0+n*mean(steps)
sig <- sqrt(n*0.25*(steps[1]-steps[2])^2)
lines(x,rep*binsize*(dnorm(x,mu,sig)), lty=2)

# diffusion using the solution by Smoluchowski
# which accounts for absorption
lines(x,rep*binsize*Smoluchowski(x,x0,0.25*(steps[1]-steps[2])^2,mean(steps),n))

}






share|cite|improve this answer














share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer








edited 20 hours ago

























answered Apr 6 at 17:48









Martijn WeteringsMartijn Weterings

15k1964




15k1964












  • $begingroup$
    "That is, independent from the assymetry parameter b of the magic tree, the probability to go bankrupt, when using the Kelly criterion, is equal to the ratio of the amount of money where the gambler goes bankrupt and the amount of money that the gambler starts with. For ten dollars and 1 cent this is a 1:1000 probability to go bankrupt" Im a bit surprised about this. So this means the probability to go bankrupt will be 1:1000 even if the payout is 10 times the offered money per round? How is this possible when the odds of going bankrupt decrease as your money grows?
    $endgroup$
    – ElectronicToothpick
    17 hours ago






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    @ElectronicToothpick If the payout is larger, and if you do not change the fraction that you gamble, then the probability to go bankrupt will be smaller. However, when you increase the fraction that you gamble, then this may not be true anymore. With the Kelly criterion, you will increase the fraction to gamble when the payout is higher. This will increase the expected value of the logarithm of the money, but as a consequence, the probability to go bankrupt will remain the same.
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    14 hours ago








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Actually, when the gambler is not using the Kelly criterion, which optimizes $E[log M_t]$, but instead chooses to optimize $E[M_t]$, then the consequence is that a higher fraction of the amount of money is being gambled. Possibly this might lead to an increase in the risk of bankruptcy when the payout is made larger. I could add an analysis of this, but I am afraid that my answer is already too long and/or complex.
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    14 hours ago




















  • $begingroup$
    "That is, independent from the assymetry parameter b of the magic tree, the probability to go bankrupt, when using the Kelly criterion, is equal to the ratio of the amount of money where the gambler goes bankrupt and the amount of money that the gambler starts with. For ten dollars and 1 cent this is a 1:1000 probability to go bankrupt" Im a bit surprised about this. So this means the probability to go bankrupt will be 1:1000 even if the payout is 10 times the offered money per round? How is this possible when the odds of going bankrupt decrease as your money grows?
    $endgroup$
    – ElectronicToothpick
    17 hours ago






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    @ElectronicToothpick If the payout is larger, and if you do not change the fraction that you gamble, then the probability to go bankrupt will be smaller. However, when you increase the fraction that you gamble, then this may not be true anymore. With the Kelly criterion, you will increase the fraction to gamble when the payout is higher. This will increase the expected value of the logarithm of the money, but as a consequence, the probability to go bankrupt will remain the same.
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    14 hours ago








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Actually, when the gambler is not using the Kelly criterion, which optimizes $E[log M_t]$, but instead chooses to optimize $E[M_t]$, then the consequence is that a higher fraction of the amount of money is being gambled. Possibly this might lead to an increase in the risk of bankruptcy when the payout is made larger. I could add an analysis of this, but I am afraid that my answer is already too long and/or complex.
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    14 hours ago


















$begingroup$
"That is, independent from the assymetry parameter b of the magic tree, the probability to go bankrupt, when using the Kelly criterion, is equal to the ratio of the amount of money where the gambler goes bankrupt and the amount of money that the gambler starts with. For ten dollars and 1 cent this is a 1:1000 probability to go bankrupt" Im a bit surprised about this. So this means the probability to go bankrupt will be 1:1000 even if the payout is 10 times the offered money per round? How is this possible when the odds of going bankrupt decrease as your money grows?
$endgroup$
– ElectronicToothpick
17 hours ago




$begingroup$
"That is, independent from the assymetry parameter b of the magic tree, the probability to go bankrupt, when using the Kelly criterion, is equal to the ratio of the amount of money where the gambler goes bankrupt and the amount of money that the gambler starts with. For ten dollars and 1 cent this is a 1:1000 probability to go bankrupt" Im a bit surprised about this. So this means the probability to go bankrupt will be 1:1000 even if the payout is 10 times the offered money per round? How is this possible when the odds of going bankrupt decrease as your money grows?
$endgroup$
– ElectronicToothpick
17 hours ago




1




1




$begingroup$
@ElectronicToothpick If the payout is larger, and if you do not change the fraction that you gamble, then the probability to go bankrupt will be smaller. However, when you increase the fraction that you gamble, then this may not be true anymore. With the Kelly criterion, you will increase the fraction to gamble when the payout is higher. This will increase the expected value of the logarithm of the money, but as a consequence, the probability to go bankrupt will remain the same.
$endgroup$
– Martijn Weterings
14 hours ago






$begingroup$
@ElectronicToothpick If the payout is larger, and if you do not change the fraction that you gamble, then the probability to go bankrupt will be smaller. However, when you increase the fraction that you gamble, then this may not be true anymore. With the Kelly criterion, you will increase the fraction to gamble when the payout is higher. This will increase the expected value of the logarithm of the money, but as a consequence, the probability to go bankrupt will remain the same.
$endgroup$
– Martijn Weterings
14 hours ago






1




1




$begingroup$
Actually, when the gambler is not using the Kelly criterion, which optimizes $E[log M_t]$, but instead chooses to optimize $E[M_t]$, then the consequence is that a higher fraction of the amount of money is being gambled. Possibly this might lead to an increase in the risk of bankruptcy when the payout is made larger. I could add an analysis of this, but I am afraid that my answer is already too long and/or complex.
$endgroup$
– Martijn Weterings
14 hours ago






$begingroup$
Actually, when the gambler is not using the Kelly criterion, which optimizes $E[log M_t]$, but instead chooses to optimize $E[M_t]$, then the consequence is that a higher fraction of the amount of money is being gambled. Possibly this might lead to an increase in the risk of bankruptcy when the payout is made larger. I could add an analysis of this, but I am afraid that my answer is already too long and/or complex.
$endgroup$
– Martijn Weterings
14 hours ago












ElectronicToothpick is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.










draft saved

draft discarded


















ElectronicToothpick is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.













ElectronicToothpick is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.












ElectronicToothpick is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.
















Thanks for contributing an answer to Cross Validated!


  • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

But avoid



  • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

  • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




draft saved


draft discarded














StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fstats.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f401480%2fthe-magic-money-tree-problem%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown





















































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown

































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown







Popular posts from this blog

How did Captain America manage to do this?

迪纳利

南乌拉尔铁路局